Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T08:03:21.960Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Incompatibility of Omniscience and Intentional Action: A Reply to David P. Hunt

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

Tomis Kapitan
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Northern Illinois University, De Kalb, Illinois 60115–2854

Extract

In ‘Omniprescient Agency’ (Religious Studies 28, 1992) David P. Hunt challenges an argument against the possibility of an omniscient agent. The argument – my own in ‘Agency and Omniscience’ (Religious Studies 27, 1991) – assumes that an agent is a being capable of intentional action, where, minimally, an action is intentional only if it is caused, in part, by the agent's intending. The latter, I claimed, is governed by a psychological principle of ‘least effort’, namely, that no one intends without antecedently feeling that (i) deliberate effort is needed to achieve desired goals, (ii) such effort has a chance of success, and (iii) it is yet contingent whether the effort will be expended and the goals realized. The goals can be anything from immediate intentional doings, tryings or basic actions, to remote and perhaps unlikely consequences of actions, e.g. global justice. The thrust of the principle is that it would be impossible for a wholly rational self-aware agent to intend without a background presumption of an open future as concerns the desired state and the means to it. But this presumption embodies a sense of contingency which, in turn, requires an acknowledged ignorance about what the future holds, otherwise the future would appear closed relative to present knowledge with the desired state presented as either guaranteed (necessary) or ruled out (impossible). Regardless whether this self-directed attitude is accurate, it follows that intentional action precludes complete knowledge of one's present and future. Consequently, no omniscient or omniprescient being can be an agent.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1994

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Bratman, M., 1987. Intention, Plans, and Practical Reason (Harvard).Google Scholar
Castañeda, H.-N., 1975. Thinking and Doing (Reidel).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldman, A., 1970. A Theory of Human Action (Princeton).Google Scholar
Hunt, D. P., 1992. ‘Omniprescient Agency’, Religious Studies, XXVIII, 351–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapitan, T., 1982. ‘On the Concept of Material Consequence’, History and Philosophy of Logic, III, 193211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapitan, T., 1989. ‘Doxastic Freedom: A Compatibilist Alternative’, American Philosophical Quarterly, XXVI, 3142.Google Scholar
Kapitan, T., 1991 a. ‘Agency and Omniscience’, Religious Studies, XXVII, 105–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kapitan, T., 1991 b. ‘Ability and Cognition: A Defense of Compatibilism’, Philosophical Studies, LXIII, 231–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mele, A., 1988. ‘Against a Belief/Desire Analysis of Intention’, Philosophia, XVII, 239–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mele, A., 1992. Springs of Action (Oxford).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Searle, J., 1983. Intentionality (Cambridge).CrossRefGoogle Scholar