Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-t5tsf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T22:45:02.442Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Can Theological Language Have Hidden Meaning?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  24 October 2008

John Morreall
Affiliation:
Assistant Professor of Philosophy, Northwestern University

Extract

Any reflective account of theological language acknowledges very early that words drawn from our experience with creatures have special meanings when applied to God. Because God transcends the created world, we cannot take predicates which apply to creatures and apply them to God without modification. And the more transcendent God is understood to be, the more modified will our language taken from creatures have to be when it is used in theology. A primitive theism which thinks of God simply as a very powerful person will view the difference between God and creatures as merely a matter of degree and not of kind. In such a view God transcends things in the world only in that he has a greater degree of the properties we find in creatures, so that predicates taken from creatures, ‘wise’ and ‘strong’, for example, can be applied to God in almost a straightforward way. The only change in meaning is that God is moreknowing and stronger. In a more sophisticated theism such as Judaism or Christianity, on the other hand, God' transcendence is seen not simply as a difference in degrees of properties, but as a difference in kind. The being God is is radically other than the kinds of beings we find in the created world. Indeed, it is sometimes claimed that God is not even ‘a being’, a thing which exists; rather God is ‘being itself’, ‘pure existence’. Aquinas, for instance, held that God does not haveproperties. God is absolutely simple, and so if we can talk about properties at all in talking about God, we have to say that God is identical to God' properties. God, too, differs radically from creatures in that he is not in time and space, nor is he dependent on anything else. But our language used with creatures is full of explicit or implicit references to time and space and to dependence, so that we cannot take our ordinary terms derived from our experience with spatio-temporal, dependent creatures and apply them straightforwardly to God.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © Cambridge University Press 1983

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

page 43 note 1 Two qualifications are required here, and will be understood in subsequent talk of words applying to God: (i) words taken from our experience with creatures must have a special sense when applied to God in true predications – we can always ‘apply’ predicates to God in their ordinary senses in false statements such as ‘God is weak’; and (2) only positive predications require special senses for their predicates – when we say ‘God is not material’, for example, we clearly mean ‘material’ in its ordinary sense.

page 44 note 1 I explore in more detail the problems facing a doctrine of analogy in Analogy and Talking about God (Washington: University Press of America, 1978).Google Scholar

page 49 note 1 Palmer, Humphrey, Analogy(London: Macmillan, 1973), p. 179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

page 50 note 1 Owen, H. P., The Christian Knowledge of God(London: University of London, Athlone Press, 1969), p. 253.Google ScholarDanielou, Cf. Jean, God and the Ways of Knowing, tr. Roberts, Walter (Cleveland: Meridian, 1957), p. 83.Google Scholar

page 50 note 2 Ross, James, ‘Analogy as a Rule of Meaning for Religious Language’, in Kenny, Anthony, ed. Aquinas(Garden City: Doubleday, Anchor Books, 1969), p. 121.Google Scholar

page 53 note 1 See e.g. David Burrell, C.S.C., Analogy and Philosophical Language (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1973), especially p. 207 and part 4;Google Scholar and Langan, Thomas, ‘Commentary on Father Clarke' Paper’, in Madden, Edward H. et al. (ed.), The Idea of God(Springfield, III.: Chas. Thomas, 1968), pp. 33–4.Google Scholar

page 53 note 2 Barth, Karl, Church Dogmatics, tr. Parker, T. H. L. et al. (Edinburgh: T. & T. Clark, 1957), II/I, section 27, esp. pp. 226–33.Google Scholar

page 53 note 3 Jerome Hamer, O.P., Karl Barth, tr. Marucca, D., S.J., , (Westminster, Md.: Newman, 1962), PP. 6977.Google Scholar

page 55 note 1 Church Dogmatics, II/I, p. 179.Google Scholar

page 55 note 2 Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1967.