Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-kw2vx Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-07T18:18:43.490Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Models for Measurement, Precision, and the Nondichotomization of Graded Responses

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2025

David Andrich*
Affiliation:
School of Education, Murdoch University
*
Requests for reprints should be sent to David Andrich, School of Education, Murdoch University, Murdoch University, Murdoch WA 6150, AUSTRALIA.

Abstract

It is common in educational, psychological, and social measurement in general, to collect data in the form of graded responses and then to combine adjacent categories. It has been argued that because the division of the continuum into categories is arbitrary, any model used for analyzing graded responses should accommodate such action. Specifically, Jansen and Roskam (1986) enunciate a joining assumption which specifies that if two categories j and k are combined to form category h, then the probability of a response in h should equal the sum of the probabilities of responses in j and k. As a result, they question the use of the Rasch model for graded responses which explicitly prohibits the combining of categories after the data are collected except in more or less degenerate cases. However, the Rasch model is derived from requirements of invariance of comparisons of entities with respect to different instruments, which might include different partitions of the continuum, and is consistent with fundamental measurement. Therefore, there is a strong case that the mathematical implication of the Rasch model should be studied further in order to understand how and why it conflicts with the joining assumption. This paper pursues the mathematics of the Rasch model and establishes, through a special case when the sizes of the categories are equal and when the model is expressed in the multiplicative metric, that its probability distribution reflects the precision with which the data are collected, and that if a pair of categories is collapsed after the data are collected, it no longer reflects the original precision. As a consequence, and not because of a qualitative change in the variable, the joining assumption is destroyed when categories are combined. Implications of the choice between a model which satisfies the joining assumption or one which reflects on the precision of the data collection considered are discussed.

Type
Original Paper
Copyright
Copyright © 1995 The Psychometric Society

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Andersen, E. B. (1973). Conditional inference for multiple choice questionnaires. British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology, 26, 3144.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andersen, E. B. (1977). Sufficient statistics and latent trait models. Psychometrika, 42, 6981.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Andrich, D. (1978). A rating formulation for ordered response categories. Psychometrika, 43, 357374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dawes, R. M. (1972). Fundamentals of attitude measurement, New York: John Wiley.Google Scholar
Fischer, G. (1977). Some probabilistic models for the description of attitudinal and behavioral changes under the influence of mass communication. In Repp, W. F., Repp, R. (Eds.), Mathematical models for social psychology (pp. 102151). Berne: Huber.Google Scholar
Fischer, G. H. (1981). On the existence and uniqueness of maximum-likelihood estimates in the Rasch model. Psychometrika, 46(1), 5977.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jansen, P. G. W., Roskam, E. E. (1984). The polychotomous Rasch model and dichotomization of graded responses. In Degreef, E., van Buggenhaut, J. (Eds.), Trends in mathematical psychology, North-Holland: Elsevier Science Publishers B. V..Google Scholar
Jansen, P. G. W., Roskam, E. E. (1986). Latent trait models and dichotomization of graded responses. Psychometrika, 51(1), 6991.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramsay, J. O. (1975). Review of Foundations of measurement, Vol. I. Psychometrika, 40, 257262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rasch, G. (1960). Probabilistic models for some intelligence and attainment tests (An expanded edition with a foreword and afterword by B. D. Wright was published in 1980 by the University of Chicago Press.), Copenhagen: Danish Institute for Educational Research.Google Scholar
Rasch, G. (1961). On general laws and the meaning of measurement in psychology. In Neyman, J. (Eds.), Proceedings of the Fourth Berkeley Symposium on Mathematical Statistics and Probability, IV (pp. 321334). Berkeley CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Rasch, G. (1966). An individualistic approach to item analysis. In Lazarsfeld, P. F., Henry, N. W. (Eds.), Readings in mathematical social science (pp. 89108). Chicago: Science Research Associates.Google Scholar
Rasch, G. (1977). On specific objectivity: An attempt at formalising the request for generality and validity of scientific statements. Danish Yearbook of Philosophy, 14, 5894.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Roskam, E. E., Jansen, P. G. W. (1989). Conditions for Rasch dichotomizability of the unidimensional polytomous Rasch model. Psychometrika, 54, 317332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thurstone, L. L. (1927). A law of comparative judgement. Psychological Review, 34, 278286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Vogt, D. K., & Wright, B. D. (Undated). Parameter Estimation for the Polychotomous Rasch Model. Unpublished manuscript. University of Chicago: School of Education.Google Scholar
Wright, B. D. (1985). Additivity in psychological measurement. Measurement and personality assessment. Selected papers, XXIII International Congress of Psychology, 8, 101111.Google Scholar