Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T06:43:56.643Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Which Universal?

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Philip L. Peterson*
Affiliation:
Syracuse University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

D.A. Armstrong’s account (1983, intimately influenced by Tooley 1977 and Swoyer 1982) of natural laws is that they are relations between universals. Armstrong doesn’t simply hold that laws are some relationships or other between universals. He also holds that they are first-order universals themselves (1983, pp. 89-90). Each ordinary law-say, causal law-is numerically identical to some first-order universal. This is a striking, seemingly incredible hypothesis. What is Armstrong thinking of when he says (1983, p. 90):

I propose that the state of affairs, the law, N(F,G), is a dyadic universal, that is, a relation, holding between states of affairs. Suppose that a particular object, a, is F, and so, because of the law N(F,G), it, a, is also G. This state of affairs, an instantiation of the law, has the form Rab, where R = N(F,G), a = a’s being F, and b, = b’s being G:

(N(F,G))(a's being F, b's being G).

Type
Part I. Confirmation and Scientific Laws
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1988

References

Armstrong, D.A. (1983). What is a Law of Nature? Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Barwise, J. and Perry, J. (1983). Situations and Attitudes. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983). How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1970). “Events and Propositions.Nous, 4, 1524.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davidson, D. (1980). Essays on Actions and Events. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: Free Press.Google Scholar
Hempel, C. (1970). Carus Lectures, I-III. Delivered at the Western Division Meetings of the American Philosophical Association, St. Louis, May 7-8.Google Scholar
Kim, J. (1973). “Causation, Nomic Subsumption and the Concept of Event.Journal of Philosophy, 20, 217236.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1979a). “On Representing Event Reference.” In Presupposition, Vol. 11 of Syntax and Semantics, pp. 325355C. Edited by Oh, K. and Dinneen, D. Academic Press.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1979b). “On the Natural Logic of Complex Event Expressions.” In Abstracts, Sections 10-12 of the 6th International Congress on Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Hannover, pp. 177-181 (complete paper), August 22-29.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1979c). “The Grimm Events of Causation.” Read to the American Philosophical Association Pacific Division Meetings, San Diego, 23 March.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1981a). “Philosophy of Language.Social Research, 47(4), 749774.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1981b). “What Causes Effects?Philosophical Studies, 39(2), 107139.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1982). “Anaphoric Reference to Facts, Propositions, and Events.Linguistics and Philosophy, 5, 235276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1984). “Semantic Indeterminacy and Scientific Underdetermination.Philosophy of Science, 51, 464487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1985a). “Causation, Agency, and Natural Actions.Proceedings of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 21(2), 204227.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1985b). “Six Grammatical Hypotheses on Actions, Causes, and ‘Cause’.” Indiana University Linguistics Club Publications, July.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1986a). “Real Logic in Philosophy.The Monist, 69(2), 236263.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1986b). “Revealing Designators and Acquaintance with Universals.Nous, 20(3), 291312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1987a). “Real Logic.” (abstract) Journal of Symbolic Logic, 52(1), 337.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1987b). “Individuating Facts, Propositions, and Events.” Abstracts, International Pragmatics Conference, Antwerp, 17-22 August.Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1987c). “Real Logic Explanation.” Proceedings, VIII International Congress for Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science, Moscow, 17-22 August. (Complete paper, pp. 505-508, in Abstracts, Vol. I.)Google Scholar
Peterson, P.L. (1987d). “Complex Events.” Revised and extended version of “A Linguistic Theory of Complex Events” read to Linguistics Colloquium, University of Oklahoma, 28 January 1980; Syracuse University.Google Scholar
Peterson, P. L. and Wali, K. (1985). “Event.Linguistic Analysis, 15(1), 318.Google Scholar
Quine, W. V. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific Explanation and the Causal Structure of the World. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Swoyer, C. (1982). “The Nature of Natural Laws.Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tooley, M. (1977). “The Nature of Laws.Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7.CrossRefGoogle Scholar