Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:15:45.440Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Truth or Consequences? Generative Versus Consequential Justification in Science

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Thomas Nickles*
Affiliation:
University of Nevada-Reno

Extract

For the past century the Central Dogma of confirmation theory has been:

All empirical support (of a theoretical claim) = empirical evidence = empirical data = successful test results = successful predictions or postdictions = true empirical consequences (of the claim plus auxiliary assumptions).

According to the Dogma, all empirical support derives from empirical testing of predicted consequences. I shall attack this pure consequentialism and defend the importance of generative justification in science.

One question which has been widely debated through the years is whether “postdicting” or explaining already known phenomena provides as much epistemic support for an hypothesis as predicting new phenomena or, indeed, whether explanation provides any support at all. I believe that explanation is on a par with prediction, but I want to address a different question here. Both explanation and prediction (as usually construed) involve consequential reasoning.

Type
Part XII. Confirmation
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

This paper is dedicated to the memory of my colleague, Willard Day, for his helpful comments and his exemplary life. I thank my co-symposiasts for a good discussion and the National Science Foundation for research support.

References

Achinstein, P. (1978), “Concepts of Evidence,” as reprinted in The Concept of Evidence. Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1983.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Blachowicz, J. (1989), “Discovery and Ampliative Inference,Philosophy of Science 56, in press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bogen, J., and Woodward, J. (1989), “Saving the Phenomena,Philosophical Review 98, in press.Google Scholar
Boole, G. (1854), An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. (1950), Logical Foundations of Probability. Chicago: University of Chicago. 2nd ed., 1962.Google Scholar
Chihara, C. (1987), “Some Problems for Bayesian Confirmation Theory.British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38: 551560.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorling, J. (1972), “Bayesianism and the Rationality of Scientific Inference,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23: 181190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dorling, J. (1973), “Demonstrative Induction: Its Significant Role in the History of Physics,Philosophy of Science 40: 360372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1983), “Testing Theoretical Hypotheses,” in Testing Scientific Theories (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 10), Earman, J. (ed.). Minneapolis: Univ. of Minnesota Press, pp. 269298.Google Scholar
Franklin, A., and Howson, C. (1985), “Newton and Kepler, A Bayesian Approach,Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 16: 379385.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton Univ. Press.Google Scholar
Hesse, M. B. (1974), The Structure of Scientific Inference. Berkeley: Univ. of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. (1982), Theory and Evidence. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press.Google Scholar
Keynes, J. M. (1921), A Treatise on Probability. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley: Univ. of California.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1980), “Why Was the Logic of Discovery Abandoned?”, in Scientific Discovery, Logic, and Rationality, Nickles, T. (ed.). Dordrecht: Reidel. Reprinted with changes in Laudan's, Science and Hypothesis. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1981, pp. 181191.Google Scholar
Mill, J. S. (1843), A System of Logic. London: Longmans, Green.Google Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1974), “Logical versus Historical Theories of Confirmation,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1984), “Positive Science and Discoverability,PSA 1984, Vol. 1, pp. 1327.Google Scholar
Nickles, T. (1985), “Beyond Divorce: Current Status of the Discovery Debate,Philosophy of Science 52: 177206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1987a), “From Natural Philosophy to Metaphilosophy of Science,” in Kelvin's Baltimore Lectures and Modern Theoretical Physics, Kargon, R. and Achinstein, P. (eds.). Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 507541.Google Scholar
Nickles, T. (1987b), “Lakatosian Heuristics and Epistemic Support,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38: 181205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Peirce, C. S. (1883), “A Theory of Probable Inference,” in Studies in Logic, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1962), “Degree of Confirmation and Inductive Logic,” reprinted in Mathematics, Matter and Method, Philosophical Papers, Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. (1978), “Ad Hocness and the Appraisal of Theories,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29: 355361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenkrantz, R. (1977), Inference, Method, and Decision. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Salmon, W. (1966), The Foundations of Scientific Inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. (1983), “Hypotheses and Mr Newton,” N. R. Hanson Memorial Lecture, Indiana University (unpublished).Google Scholar