Hostname: page-component-745bb68f8f-l4dxg Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-01-13T23:24:50.079Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Toward a Historical Meta-Method for Assessing Normative Methodologies: Rationability, Serendipity, and the Robinson Crusoe Fallacy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Stephen J. Wykstra*
Affiliation:
University of Tulsa

Extract

During the past two decades, much philosophy of science has been focused on issues about the norms and methods by which scientific theories are rationally appraised; and increasingly, philosophers have turned to history of science as a touchstone for assessing normative methodologies purporting to elucidate scientific rationality. But even among such historical methodologists, there is much disagreement and unclarity about how historical study of science can arbitrate between rival methodological theories; and until progress is made at this meta-methodological level, the very legitimacy of this role for history will remain controversial. (Keynotes in the controversy are sounded in Kuhn (1970b , pp. 235—41; Lakatos (1971); Giere (1973); McMullin (1976); Burian (1977); and Laudan (1977, pp. 158-63).) This paper begins by arguing that the meta-method implicit in much historical methodology is different from the explicit meta-methodology most often touted.

Type
Part VIII. History and the Metaphilosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1980 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I wish to thank Larry Laudan and Philip Quinn for their comnents on the dissertation chapter from which this paper is abstracted.

References

Buck, Roger C. and Cohen, Robert S. (eds.). (1971). PSA 1970. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 8). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Burian, Richard. (1977). “More than a Marriage of Convenience: On the Inextricability of History and Philosophy of Science.Philosophy of Science 44: 142.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, L. J. (1975). “How Empirical is Contemporary Logical Empiricism?Philosophia 5: 299315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Creary, Lewis. (1971). “Empiricism and Rationality.Synthese 23: 234–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feyerabend, Paul. (1975). Against Method. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Giere, Ronald. (1973). “History and Philosophy of Science: Intimate Relationship or Marriage of Convenience?British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24: 282–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, Adolf. (1975). “Falsifiability and Rationality.” Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Hall, Richard J. (1971). “Can We Use the History of Science to Decide Between Competing Methodologies?” In Buck and Cohen (1971). Pages 151-9.Google Scholar
Howson, Colin (ed.). (1976). Method and Appraisal in the Physical Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. (1970a). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Second Enlarged Edition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas. (1970b). “Reflections on My Critics.” In Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. Edited by Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 231-78.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakatos, Imre. (1971). “History of Science and Its Rational Reconstructions.” In Buck and Cohen (1971). Pages 91136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. (1976). “Two Dogmas of Methodology.Philosophy of Science 43 : 585-96.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. (1977). Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, Larry. (1979). “A Refutation of Convergent Realism.” Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Maull, Nancy. (1976). “Reconstructed Science as Philosophical Evidence.” In Suppe and Asquith (1976). Pages 119-29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McMullin, Ernan. (1976). “History and Philosophy of Science: A Marriage of Convenience?” In PSA 1974. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 32.) Edited by Cohen, R. S., et al. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 585602.Google Scholar
Millman, Arthur B. (1976). “The Plausibility of Research Programmes.” In Suppe and Asquith (1976). Pages 140-50.Google Scholar
Musgrave, Alan. (1976). “Method or Madness?” In Essays in Honor of Imre Lakatos. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 34.) Edited by Cohen, R. S., Feyerabend, P. K., and Wartofsky, M. W.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 457491.Google Scholar
Quinn, Philip. (1972). “Methodological Appraisal and Heuristic AdviceStudies in History and Philosophy of Science 3: 135–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Suppe, F. and Asquith, P. (eds.). (1976). PSA 1976, Vol 1. E. Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Worrall, John (1976). “Thomas Young and the ‘Refutation’ of Newtonian Optics: A Case-Study in the Interaction of Philosophy of Science and History of Science.” In Howson (1976). Pages 107-79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wykstra, Stephen. (1978). The Interdependence of History of Science and Philosophy of Science: Toward a Meta-Theory of Scientific Rationality. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Pittsburgh.Google Scholar