Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T17:22:16.849Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Status and Meaning of the Laws of Inertia

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Robert Alan Coleman
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics & Statistics, Department of Philosophy, University of Regina, Regina S4S 0A2
Herbert Korte
Affiliation:
Department of Mathematics & Statistics, Department of Philosophy, University of Regina, Regina S4S 0A2

Extract

A great deal of literature on the status and meaning of the Laws of Inertia in spacetime theories has nurtured and given wide currency to the claim that the laws are conventional in character, that they are definitions, or circular and without empirical content.

Philosophers who argue for the conventional character of the laws, do so, either emphasizing epistemological or ontological considerations concerning the structure of spacetime.

Those who argue for their conventional character mainly on epistemic grounds, point out, that the laws do not supply independent criteria of what is to count as force-free or natural motion. The only way of knowing when no forces act on a body is that it moves as a free particle traveling along the geodesies of spacetime. But how, without already knowing the geodetic structure of spacetime is one to determine which particles are free and which are not?

Type
Part VI. Philosophy of Physics
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Coleman, R.A. and Korte, H. (1980). “Jet Bundles and Path Structures.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 21: 13401351. Erratum- 23: 345 (1982).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, R.A. and Korte, H. (1981a). “Spacetime G-Structures and their Prolongations.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 22: 25982611.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Coleman, R.A. and Korte, H. (1981b). “A Realist Field Ontology of the Causal-Inertial Structure.” Unpublished University of Regina preprint.Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Friedmann, M. (1973). “The Meaning and Status of Newton's Law of Inertia and the Nature of Gravitational Forces.” Philosophy of Science 40: 329359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehlers, J. et al. (1972). “The Geometry of Free Fall and Light Propagation.” In General Relativity, Papers in Honour of J.L. Synge. Edited by O'Raifeartaigh, L.. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Pages 6384.Google Scholar
Ehlers, J. (1973). “Survey of General Relativity Theory.” In Relativity, Astrophysics and Cosmology. Edited by Israel, W.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 1125.Google Scholar
Ehlers, J. and Schild, A. (1973). “Geometry in a Manifold with Projective Structure.” Communications in Mathematical Physics 32: 119146.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehlers, J. and Kohler, E. (1977). “Path Structures on Manifolds.” Journal of Mathematical Physics 18: 20142018.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ehresmann, C. (1951-52). “Les Prolongements d'une Variete Differentiable, I-V.” Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Séances de l'Académic des Sciences 233: 598600. 777-779, 1081-1083. 234: 1028-1030, 1424-1425.Google Scholar
Einstein, A. (1919). What is the Theory of Relativity?The London Times November 28, 1919. (As reprinted in Essays in Science. New York: Philosophical Library, 1934. Pages 5360.)Google Scholar
Einstein, A. (1970). “Remarks Concerning the Essays Brought Together in this Co-operative Volume.” In Albert Einstein Philosopher-Scientist, Vol. II. Edited by Schilpp, P.A.. LaSalle, Illinois: Open Court Press. Pages 665688.Google Scholar
Ellis, B. (1965). “The Origin and Nature of Newton's Law of Motion.” In Beyond the Edge of Certainty. (University of Pittsburgh Serie3 in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 2.) Edited by Colodny, R.G.. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Pages 2968.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1973). “General Relativity, Geometrodynamics and Ontology.” In Philosophical Problems in Space and Time. 2nd enlarged edition. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume XII. Edited by Cohen, R.S. and Wartofsky, Marx.) Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 728803.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1977). “Absolute and Relational Theories.” In Foundations of Space-Time Theories. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume VIII.) Edited by Earman, J., et al. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 303373.Google Scholar
Hanson, N.R. (1965). “Newton's First Law: A Philosopher's Door into Natural Philosophy.” In Beyond the Edge of Certainty. (University of Pittsburgh Series in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 2.) Edited by Colodny, R.G.. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice Hall. Pages 628.Google Scholar
Hooker, C.A. (1974). “Defense of a Non-Conventionalist Interpretation of Classical Mechanics.” In Logical and Epistemological Studies in Contemporary Physics. (Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume XIII.) Edited by Cohen, Robert S. and Wartofsky, Marx W.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 123191.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hunt, I.E. and Suchting, W.A. (1969). “Force and Natural Motion.” Philosophy of Science 36: 233251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kobayashi, S. and Nomizu, K. (1963). Foundations of Differential Geometry, Volume I. New York: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Munkres, J.R. (1963). Elementary Differential Topology. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nijenhuis, A. (1972). “Natural Bundles and Their General Properties.” In Differential Geometry: In Honour of Kentaro Yano. Edited by Kobayashi, S., et al. Tokyo: Kinokuniya Book-Store Co. Pages 317334.Google Scholar
Pommaret, J.F. (1978). Systems of Partial Differential Equations and Lie Pseudogroups. New York: Gordon and Breach.Google Scholar
Porteous, I.R. (1969). Topological Geometry. London: Van Nostrand Reinhold.Google Scholar
H., Reichenbach (1969). Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1977). “The Curvature of Physical Space.” In Foundations of Space-Time Theories. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume VIII.) Edited by Earman, J., et al. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 281302.Google Scholar
Sklar, L. (1977). “Facts, Conventions and Assumptions.” In Foundations of Space-Time Theories. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume VIII.) Edited by Earman, J., et al. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 206274.Google Scholar
Trautman, A. (1966). “The General Theory of Relativity.” Usnekhi Fizicheskikh Nauk 89: 337. (English translation: Soviet Physics Uspekhi 9: 319-339.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weyl, H. (1922a). Raum, Zeit, Materie. 4th ed. Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer-Verlag. (As reprinted as Space-Time-Matter. (trans.) Brose, H.L.. New York: Dover, 1952.)Google Scholar
Weyl, H. (1922b). “Zur Infinitesimalgeometrie: Einordnung der projektiven und konformen Auffassung.” In Nachrichten von der Königlichen Gesellsohaft der Wissenschaften zu Göttingen, Mathematisch-physicalische Klasse aus dem Jahre 1921. Pages 99-112. (As reprinted in Gesammelte Abhandlungen, Volume II. Berlin-Heidelberg-New York: Springer-Verlag, 1968. Pages 195207.)Google Scholar
Weyl, H. (1923). Mathematische Analyse des Raum Problems. Berlin: J. Springer. (As reprinted in Das Kontiuum und Andere Monographien. H. Weyl, et al. New York: Chelsea, 1960.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weyl, H. (1927). Philosophic der Mathematik und Naturwissenschaft. (Handbuch der Philosophie.) München und Berlin: R. Oldenbourg. (As reprinted as the revised and augmented English edition: Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science, (trans.) Helmer, O.. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1949.)Google Scholar
Winnie, J.A. (1977). “The Causal Theory of Space-Time.” In Foundations of Space-Time Theories. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume VIII.) Edited by Earman, J., et al. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Pages 134205.Google Scholar