Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T18:33:40.254Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Some Twists in the Cognitive Turn

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Steve Fuller*
Affiliation:
Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Contrary to what the name suggests, the recent work of Howard Margolis (1987) and Ronald Giere (1988) demonstrates that the “cognitive turn” in the philosophy of science is not simply the application of cognitive science to the study of science. For one thing, neither one is what Jerry Fodor (1981) has called a “methodological solipsist,” that is, someone who wants to account for thought processes without presupposing an account of the world of which those thoughts are about. Margolis, in fact, comes perilously close to Fodor’s anti-cognitivist foe, J. J. Gibson (1979), whose “ecological” perspective requires that an organism’s thought processes be specified in terms of structures in the environment, “affordances,” capable of satisfying the organism’s desire to know. The Margolian focus on overcoming “barriers” to alternative “habits of mind,” as the psychic basis of Kuhn’s paradigm shifts, only serves to highlight this broadly “functional” side of thinking that typically has no place in cognitive science.

Type
Part XI. Implications of the Cognitive Sciences for Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1991

References

Byrne, R. and Whiten, A. (eds.) (1987), Machiavellian Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1981), Representations. Cambridge MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, S. (1989), Philosophy of Science and Its Discontents. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Fuller, S. (forthcoming), “Naturalized Epistemology Sublimated,Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22.Google Scholar
Gibson, J. J. (1979), The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lakoff, R. (1987), Women, Fire, and Dangerous Things. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Margolis, H. (1987), Patterns, Thinking, and Cognition. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Nersessian, N. (1984), Faraday to Einstein. Dordrecht: Nijhoff.Google Scholar
Wicklund, R. (1989), “The Appropriation of Ideas,” in Psychology of Group Influence, Paulus, P. (ed.). Hillsdale NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum, pp. 393424.Google Scholar
Wrong, D. (1961), “The Oversocialized Conception of Man,American Sociological Review 26: 184193.CrossRefGoogle Scholar