Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-mkpzs Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:18:49.263Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Scientific Realism and the Hierarchical Counterfactual Path from Data to Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Ronald Laymon*
Affiliation:
The Ohio State University

Extract

Philosophers tend to view the relationship between a particular scientific theory and its data as representable by means of a single logical structure. The relationship is not ordinarily viewed as requiring a hierarchy of structures of different logical type. Two recent and excellent books illustrate this tendency. Glymour in Theory and Evidence (1980) continues the positivist tradition of viewing theories as axiomatic systems which connect with their evidence by means of ordinary quantification and truth functional connectives. Theory testing can be understood in terms of the syntactic properties of a single logical system. In The Scientific Image (1980), van Fraassen adopts a version of what is sometimes called the “semantic view”: a theory is a set of models of some purely formal system. Evidence constitutes (if confirmatory) a sub-model imbedded in a model of the equivalence class that is the theory.

Type
Part III. Scientific Realism and Observation
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Boyd, R. (1981). “Scientific Realism and Naturalistic Epistemology. In PSA 1980, Volume 2. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and R.N., Giere. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 613662.Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Glymour, C. (1980). “Relativity and Eclipses: The British Eclipse Expeditions of 1919 and Their Predecessors.” Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 11: 49—85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980). Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Humphrey, S.F. (1981). An Anti-Realist Conception of Theories in Mathematical Physics. Unpublished Ph.D. Dissertation, Ohio State University.Google Scholar
Jeans, Sir J. (1940). An Introduction to the Kinetic Theory of Gases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Koertge, N. (1973). “Theory Change in Science.” In Conceptual Change. Edited by Pearce, G. and Maynard, P.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 167198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981). “A Confutation of Convergent Realism.” Philosophy of Science 48: 1949.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laymon, R. (1977). “Newton's Advertised Precision and His Refutation of the Received Laws of Refraction.” In Studies in Perception: Interrelations in History and Philosophy of Science. Edited by Machamer, P.K. and Turnbull, R.G.. Columbus: The Ohio State University Press. Pages 231258.Google Scholar
Laymon, R. (1978a). “Feyerabend, Brownian Motion, and the Hiddenness of Refuting Facts.” Philosophy of Science 44: 225247.10.1086/288740CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laymon, R. (1978b). “Newton's Experimentum Crucis and the Logic of Idealization and Theory Refutation.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 9: 5177.10.1016/0039-3681(78)90021-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laymon, R. (1980). “Idealization, Explanation, and Confirmation.” In PSA 1980. Volume 1. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and Giere, R.N.. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 336352.Google Scholar
Laymon, R. (1983). “Newton's Demonstration of Universal Gravitation and Philosophical Theories of Confirmation.” In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume 11. Edited by Earman, John. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Forthcoming.Google Scholar
Newton, I. (1687). Philosophiae Naturalis Principia Mathematica. London: Royal Society. (As reprinted as Sir Isaac Newton's Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy and his System of the World. 2 vols. (trans.) A. Motte, revised by F. Cajori. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975). “What is Mathematical Truth?In Mathematics. Matter and Method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 6078.Google Scholar
Smart, J.J.C. (1963). Philosophy and Scientific Realism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1962). “Models of Data.” In Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science: Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress. Edited by Nagel, E., et al. Stanford: Stanford University Press. Pages 252261.Google Scholar
Synge, J.L. (1960). Relativity: The General Theory. Amsterdam: North Holland.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B.C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Klüber, H. (1960). “The Determination of Einstein‘s Light-Deflection in the Gravitational Field of the Sun.” In Vistas in Astronomy. Volume III. Edited by Beer, A.. London: Pergamon Press. Pages 4777.Google Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1972). Gravitation and Cosmology. New York: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, W.C. (1981). “Robustness, Reliability and Multiple-Determination in Science.” In Scientific Inquiry and the Social Sciences: A Volume in Honor of Donald T. Campbell. Edited by Brewer, M. and Collins, B.. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass. Pages 124163.Google Scholar