Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:59:03.193Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Science, Certainty, and Descartes

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Gary Hatfield*
Affiliation:
University of Pennsylvania

Extract

It is difficult to determine the place of experience in Descartes’ philosophy and science. His a priori, rationalist metaphysics would seem, on the face of it, difficult to reconcile with the explicit appeal he makes to sensory evidence in both his scientific practice and methodological remarks. Although earlier descriptions of Descartes as a pure a priorist in natural science (e.g., Koyré 1978, pp. 89-94) have rightly been rejected, it would be a mistake to embrace the other extreme, as does Clarke (1982), with his bold revisionist thesis that Descartes was, in actuality, an empiricist. And yet the possibility of combining the rationalist and empiricist elements in Descartes’ thought has also seemed problematic, for it has been assumed that Descartes required that experientially based knowledge meet the standard of absolute certainty set by the the method of doubt in the First Meditation (Garber 1978).

Type
Part VIII. Descartes
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Beck, J. (1952). The Method of Descartes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Beck, J. (1965). The Metaphysics of Descartes. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Buchdahl, G. (1969). Metaphysics and the Philosophy of Science. The Classical Origins: Descartes to Kant. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Clarke, D. (1982). Descartes’ Philosophy of Science. Manchester Manchester University Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1964-74). Ouevres de Descartes. Edited by Adam, C. and Tannery, P.. New edition. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1965). Discourse on Method, Optics, Geometry, and Meteorology. Translated by Olscamp, P.. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1970). Philosophical Letters. Translated by Kenny, Anthony. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1983). Principles of Philosophy. Translated by Miller, V. and Miller, R.. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Descartes, R. (1984-5). Philosophical Writings. Translated by Cottingham, J., Stoothoff, R. and Murdoch, D.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Galison, P. (1984). “Descartes's Comparisons.Isis 75: 311326.Google Scholar
Garber, D. (1978). “Science and Certainty in Descartes.” In Descartes: Critical and Interpretive Essays. Edited by Hooker, M.. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, pp. 114151.Google Scholar
Garber, D. (1987). “Descartes et la Methode en 1637.” In Le Discours et sa Methode. Edited by Grimaldi, N. and Marion, J.. Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, pp. 6587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gueroult, M. (1984-5). Descartes’ Philosophy Interpreted According to the Order of Reasons. Translated by Ariew, R.. 2 vols. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. (1979). “Force (God) in Descartes’ Physics.Studies in History and Philosophy of Science. 10: 113140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, G. (1985). “First Philosophy and Natural Philosophy in Descartes.” In Philosophy, Its History and Historiography. Edited by Holland, A. J.. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 149164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, G. (1986). “The Senses and the Fleshless Eye: The Meditations as Cognitive Exercises.” In Articles on Descartes’ Meditations. Edited by Rorty, Amèlie. Berkeley: University of California Press, pp. 4579.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hatfield, G. (in press). “Metaphysics and the New Science.” In Reappraisals of the Scientific Revolution. Edited by Lindberg, D. and Westman, R.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hatfield, G. (forthcoming). “Reason, Nature, and God in Descartes.” Science in Context.Google Scholar
Koyré, A. (1978). Galileo Studies. Translated by Mepham, J.. New Jersey: Humanities Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1966). “The Clock Metaphor and Probabilism.Annals of Science. 22:73104.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schuster, J. (1980). “Descartes, Mathesis Universalis, 1619-28.” In Descartes: Philosophy, Mathematics and Physics. Edited by Gaukroger, S.. New Jersey: Barnes and Noble, pp. 4196.Google Scholar
Schuster, J. (1986). “Cartesian Method as Mythic Speech: A Diachronic and Structural Analysis.” In The Politics and Rhetoric of Scientific Method. Edited by Schuster, J. and Yeo, R.. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 3395.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, A. (1987). “Descartes's Theory of Light and Refraction: A Discourse on Method.Transactions of the American Philosophical Society. Vol. 77, Part 3.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, B. (1978). Descartes: The Project of Pure Inquiry. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar