Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:12:39.276Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Saving the Differences: Gadamer and Rorty

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Charles B. Guignon*
Affiliation:
The University of Texas at Austin

Extract

Professor Bernstein has shown how, coming from three distinct orientations in twentieth century philosophy, Gadamer, Habermas and Rorty have arrived at strikingly similar conclusions. The upshot of their thought, as Professor Bernstein points out, is a powerful critique of traditional foundationalism. There is no uninterpreted “given”, no theory-neutral set of “facts”, no timeless structure of reason, no disinterested vantage point for research, outside of the interpretations and interests of the community of interpreters that are embodied in our current social practices. The collapse of the bad old dream of firm foundations and of ultimate convergence on the truth is taken as a fait accompli by Bernstein. The question that confronts us now is what to make of this situation. On the face of it there appear to be two types of stance open to us.

Type
Part VII. Recent American and Continental Developments
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Bernstein, Richard. (1980). “Philosophy in the Conversation of Mankind.” Review of Metaphysics 23: 745-775.Google Scholar
Bernstein, Richard. (1982). “From Hermeneutics to Practice.” Review of Metaphysics 35: 823-845.Google Scholar
Bernstein, Richard. (1983). “What is the Difference that Hakes a Difference? Gadamer, Habermas, and Rorty.” In PSA 1982. Volume 2. Edited by P.D. Asquith and T. Nickles. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 331-359.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. (1963). Le Probleme de la conscience historique. Louvain: Institut Superieur de Philosophie, Université Catholique de Louvain. (As reprinted as “The Problem of Historical Consciousness.” In Interpretive Social Science: A Reader. Edited by P. Rabinow and W.M. Sullivan, (trans.) J.L. Close. Berkeley: University of California Press,. 1979. Pages 103-160.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. (1965). Wahrheit und Methode. 2nd ed. Tübingen: Mohr. (As reprinted as Truth and Method, (trans.) Barden, G. and Cumming, J.. New York: Seabury Press, 1975.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. (1972). “Das Ontologisehe Problem des Wertes.” In Human Sciences and the Problem of Values. Hague: Nijhoff. Pages 17-31. (As reprinted in Kleine Schriften. Volume 4. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr, 1977. Pages 205-217.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. (1974). “Was ist Praxis? Die Bedingungen gesellschaftlicher Vernunft.” Universitas Heft 11: 1143-1158. (As reprinted as “What is Practice? The Conditions of Social Reason.” In Gadamer (1981). Pages 69-87.Google Scholar
Gadamer, H.-G. (1981). Reason in the Age of Science. (trans.) Lawrence, F.G. . Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard. (1979). Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard. (1981a). “Heidegger Against the Pragmatists.” Paper delivered at the Second Guy L. Leonard Memorial Conference in Philosophy (“Hermeneutics”). October 14. University of Nevada at Reno. (Unpublished).Google Scholar
Rorty, Richard. (1981b). “Nineteenth-Century Idealism and Twentieth-Century Textualism.” The Monist 4: 155-174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar