Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:54:39.774Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reduction and Realism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Margaret Morrison*
Affiliation:
Stanford University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

In his recent book Foundations of Space-Time Theories Michael Friedman argues for a realism about theoretical structure based on specific methodological practices concerning theory unification. Theoretical structures that are essential to the unifying process are to be given a literal realistic interpretation while the remaining ones can be considered as having merely representational status. Friedman’s account of unification involves the notion of a literal reduction or identification of observational properties of entities or objects with their theoretical counterparts. The relationship between these two levels of theory can be construed as that of submodel to model. Once the appropriate reductions are achieved we are then free to conjoin certain theoretical structures with others thereby enabling us, over time, to produce a unified theory encompassing a variety of domains.

The alternative to this view Friedman describes as the representationalist approach. Instead of characterizing the relationship between observational and theoretical structures as that of submodel to model the observational properties are simply correlated by way of an embedding (as opposed to an identity) map with their appropriate theoretical counterparts.

Type
Part IX. Interpreting Scientific Inference
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1988

References

Brush, S. (1976). The Kind of Motion We Call Heat. Books 1 and 2. Amsterdam: North Holland Press.Google Scholar
Collie, C.H. (1982). Kinetic Theory and Entropy. New York: Longman Group.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1983). Foundations of Space-Time Theories. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Gitterman, M. and Halpern, V. (1981). Qualitative Analyses of Physical Problems. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Khinchin, A.I. (1949). Mathematical Foundations of Statistical Mechanics. New York: Dover Books.Google Scholar
Klein, M. (1974). “The Historical Origins of the Van Der Waals Equation.” In Physica 73: 2847.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1979). The Structure of Science. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Suppes, P. (1961). “A Comparison of the Meaning and Uses of Models in Mathematics and the Empirical Sciences.” In The Concept and Role of the Model in Mathematics in the Natural and Social Sciences pp. 163177. Edited by Freudenthal, H.. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co.Google Scholar
Tabor, D. (1979). Gasses, Liquids and Solids. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, F. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: The Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar