Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:18:37.492Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Natural Selection, Hypercycles and the Origin of Life

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Sahotra Sarkar*
Affiliation:
University of Chicago
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Over the last eighteen years Manfred Eigen and his co-workers have postulated a new theory about the origin of life on earth that has presented a detailed account of how many of the features of extant living organisms (such as a universal genetic code and protein-nucleic acid interdependence) might have arisen from purely physical interactions.2 This theory is critically based on the special dynamical properties of certain chemical cycles called “hypercycles” which cause some of them to exhibit hyperbolic growth over time while undergoing selection. The purpose of this paper is to separate two aspects of this theory and then to study the first one in greater detail. The first aspect consists of a physical account of evolution by natural selection at the molecular level that depends only on the kinetics of certain chemical systems and can be applied to a variety of such systems. The second consists of the special dynamical properties that are exhibited when this account is applied, specifically, to hypercycles.

Type
Part VII. Biology
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1988

Footnotes

1

Thanks are due to William C. Wimsatt for comments on an earlier draft of this paper.

References

Bernstien, H., Byerly, H. C., Hopf, H. A., Michod, R. A., Vemulapalli, G. K. (1983). “The Darwinian Dynamic.The Quarterly Review of Biology 58: 185207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyson, Freeman. (1985). Origins of Life. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Eigen, Manfred. (1971). “Selforganization of Matter and the Evolution of Biological Macromolecules.Die Naturwissenschaften 58: 465523.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Eigen, Manfred and Peter, Schuster (1979). The Hypercycle. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-642-67247-7CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Küppers, Bernd-Olaf. (1983). Molecular Theory of Evolution. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.10.1007/978-3-642-70544-1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewontin, Richard. (1970). “The Units of Selection.Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 118.10.1146/annurev.es.01.110170.000245CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayr, Ernst. (1982). The Growth of Biological Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, Alexander. (1985). The Structure of Biological Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sarkar, Sahotra. (1987). “Reductionism and Functional Explanation in Molecular Biology.” Submitted to Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science.Google Scholar
Sarkar, Sahotra. (1988). “Reductionism and Molecular Biology: A Reappraisal.” Ph. D. Dissertation. Department of Philosophy. University of Chicago. In preparation.Google Scholar
Thompson, Colin J. and McBride, John L. (1974). “On Eigen’s Theory of the Self-Organization of Matter and the Evolution of Biological Macromolecules.Mathematical Biosciences 21: 127142.10.1016/0025-5564(74)90110-2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William C. (1972). “Teleology and the Logical Structure of Function Statements.Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 3: 180.Google Scholar