Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:04:10.008Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Individuality and Macroevolutionary Theory

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Marc Ereshefsky*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

The issue of whether species are individuals is now an old one; the literature abounds with arguments, counter-arguments and counter-counter-arguments for their individuality. The question I want to take up in this paper is not whether species are indeed individuals, but what ramifications their alleged individuality has for macroevolutionary theory.

According to those biologists who argue for a new theory of macroevolution, the individuality of species is one of the fundamental premises of that theory. For example, Joel Cracraft writes of himself and others that

The issue of individuality… is at the heart of arguments of those evolutionary biologists who see a need to view the patterns and processes of evolution as being hierarchically arranged into microevolutionary and macroevolutionary levels (1987, p. 332).

Type
Part VII. Biology
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1988

Footnotes

1

I want to thank Elliott Sober for his constant help and encouragement, and David Hull for his comments on an earlier version of this paper.

References

Ayala, F. (1983). “Beyond Darwinism? The Challenge of Macroevolution to the Synthetic Theory of Evolution,” in PSA 1982, Volume 2, pp. 275-292. Edited by Asquith, P. and Nickles, T. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Cracraft, J. (1987) “Species Concepts and the Ontology of Evolution,Biology and Philosophy 2: 329346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eldredge, N. (1985). Unfinished Synthesis, New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Eldredge, N. and Cracraft, J. (1980). Phylogenetic Patterns and the Evolutionary Process, New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Ereshefsky, M. (1988a) “The Ontological Status of Species: A Study of Individuality and its Role in Evolutionary Theory,” University of Wisconsin PhD. Thesis.Google Scholar
Ereshefsky, M. (1988b). “Discussion: Axiomatics and Individuality: A Reply to Williams’ ‘Species are Individuals’,” Philosophy of Science: forthcoming.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ghiselin, M. (1987). “Species Concepts, Individuality, and Objectivity,Biology and Philosophy 2: 127143.Google Scholar
Hennig, W. (1966). Phylogenetic Systematics, Urbana: University of Illinois.Google Scholar
Hull, D. (1980). “Individuality and Selection,Annual Review Ecology and Systematic 11: 311332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hull, D. (1981). “Units of Evolution: A Metaphysical Essay,” in The Philosophy of Evolution. Edited by Jensen, U.J. and Harre, R.’. New York: St. Martins Press, pp. 2344.Google Scholar
Mayr, E. (1987). “The Ontological Status of Species: Scientific Progress and Philosophical Terminology,Biology and Philosophy 2: 145166.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1985). The Structure of Biological Science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1987). “Why Does the Nature of Species Matter? Comments on Ghiselin and Mayr,Biology and Philosophy 2: 192197.Google Scholar
Smart, J.J. (1963). Philosophy and Scientific Realism, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1984). The Nature of Selection, Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Williams, G.C. (1966). Adaptation and Natural Selection, Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar