Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-hc48f Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T19:36:50.649Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

How Scientists reach Agreement about new Observations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

David Gooding*
Affiliation:
Science Studies Centre, University of Bath
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Epistemology has been socialised. Cognitive and social interactions between observers are now as important as their interventions into the course of nature. This contrasts with traditional views of how we get natural facts into our discourse about nature. These assumed the efficacy of individual observers’ causal interactions with the natural world, making their interactions with other observers irrelevant. Kant’s conclusion that empirical access depends also upon our concepts did not challenge the individualistic character of the epistemology of science. Observers’ agreement about their observations showed that each individual can have independent perceptual access to one and the same world.

Historical and sociological studies of science show that social and procedural aspects of observation in the laboratory make an essential contribution to consensus about observations (see Knorr-Cetina and Mulkay (1983) and Gooding (1985a).

Type
Part IV. General Philosophy Of Science (A)
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1986

References

Barnes, B. (1983). “Social life as bootstrapped induction.” Sociology 17: 521545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Davy, H. (1821). “On the magnetic phenomena produced by Electricity.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society 111; 719.Google Scholar
Faraday, M. (1821-22). “Historical Sketch of Electromagnetism.” Annals of Philosophy 2; 195-200, 274-290; 3: 107121.Google Scholar
Faraday, M. (1931). Faraday’s Diary Volume 1. (ed.) T. Martin. London: Bell.Google Scholar
Gooding, D. (1985a). “Experiment and concept formation in electromagnetic science and technology.” History and Technology 2: 151176.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gooding, D. (1985b). “In nature’s school: Faraday as an experimentalist.” In Faraday Rediscovered. Edited by D. Gooding and F. James. London and New York: MacMillan/Stockton. Pages 105-135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goodman, N. (1978). Ways of Worldmaking. Hassocks: Harvester.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Heilbron, J. (1981). “The electric field before Faraday.” In Conceptions of Ether. Edited by G. Cantor and M. Hodges. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Pages 187213.Google Scholar
Knorr-Cetina, K. and Mulkay, M. (eds.). (1983). Science Observed. Beverly Hills and London Sage.Google Scholar
Quine, H.V.O. (1960). Word and Object. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
Quine, H.V.O. (1973). The Roots of Reference. La Salle: Open Court.Google Scholar
von Wright, G.H. (1971). Explanation and Understanding. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar