Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:03:53.547Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Hidden Agendas: Knowledge and Verification

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Joia Lewis*
Affiliation:
University of San Diego
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Schlick has been accused of a number of philosophical sins over the years, most notably his rather casual, and frequent, traversing of the borders between language, experience, and reality. While we allow our scientists the freedom to roam creatively throughout the peripheral regions of Epistemology and Metaphysics, we are not so tolerant of our philosophers. We know that Schlick gave up the physics laboratory for the philosopher’s armchair, and we expect him to stick to a particular position.

Schlick’s colleagues in the Vienna Circle were not totally blameless in this regard, either, and it may be that part of the charm of their work is precisely their inability to stick to the positions that solidified over 2500 years of western philosophy.

Type
Part IV. History of Philosophy of Science
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1991

References

Churchland, P. S. (1986), Neurophilosophy, Toward a Unified science of the Mind/Brain.. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Coffa, J. A. (forthcoming) The Semantic Tradition from Kant to Carnap: To the Vienna Station..Google Scholar
Edelman, G. (1987), Neural Darwinism, The Theory of Neuronal Group Selection. New York: Basic Books, Inc.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1983), “Moritz Schlick, Philosophical Papers”, Philosophy of Science.. 50: 498514.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gadol, E. (ed.) (1982) Rationality and Science, A Memorial Volume for Moritz Schlick in Celebration of the Centennial of His birth. Wien: Springer-Verlag.Google Scholar
Haller, R. (ed.) (1982), Schlick und Neurath—ein Symposion, Grazer philosophische Studien. 16/17. Rodopi, Amsterdam.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oberdan, T., (1989), “Conventionalism in the Protocol Sentence Controversy: The Case for Schlick”. (manuscript)Google Scholar
Ryckman, T., (1990), “Conditio Sine Qua Non? The Concept of Zuordnung. in the Early Epistemologies of Cassirer and Schlick”. (manuscript)CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schlick, M. (1985), General Theory of Knowledge. La Salle, Illinois: Open Court Publishing Co. Translation by Blumberg, A.E. of Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre.., Second German edition (1925).Google Scholar
Schlick, M. (1978), Philosophical Papers., Volume I (1901-1922), ed. by Mulder, H.L. and van de Velde-Schlick, B., Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Schlick, M. (l978),.Philosophical Pape., Volume II (1925-1936), ed. by Mulder, H.L. and van de Velde-Schlick, B., Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Schlick, M. (1987), The Problems of Philosophy in their Interconnection.., Winter Semester Lectures, (1933-34), ed. by Mulder, H. L. , Kox, A. J. , and Hegselmann, R. , transl. by Peter Heath (Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar