Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-jn8rn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:52:33.726Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Habermas and the Natural Sciences

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Gary Gutting*
Affiliation:
University of Notre Dame
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Habermas’ fundamental philosophical project is to reinstate, in a contemporary context, the classical idea that human lives can be guided by practical knowledge; i.e., that it is possible to know what are the ultimate human values and direct our lives in accord with this knowledge:2 This project has a central importance because of the ironic turn taken by the development of contemporary society. Previously, societies generally thought they had a clear and rationally founded notion of the ultimate values that should guide human lives; but they lacked the technical resources needed to implement (or remove obstacles to) these values. Today, we have the technical resources to at least make a significant effort toward the realization of our values. But the very scientific advances that have provided these technical resources have called into question the rational bases of traditional values and even led to the suggestion—urged by the positivists—that our ultimate values have no cognitive status but are merely irrational givens.

Type
Part X. Habermas
Copyright
Copyright © 1981 Philosophy of Science Association

Footnotes

1

I am grateful to Karl Ameriks, Fred Dallmayr, Mary Hesse, Larry Simon, and Jerry Wallulis for comments on the original version of this paper.

References

[1] Delaney, C.F., et al. The Synoptic Vision: Essays on the Philosophy of Wilfrid Sellars. Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1977.Google Scholar
[2] Gutting, G.Continental Philosophy of Science.” In Current Research in Philosophy of Science. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and Kyburg, H. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association, 1979. Pages 94117.Google Scholar
[3] Habermas, J. Knowledge and Human Interests. (trans.) Shapiro, J.J. Boston: Beacon Press, 1971. (Originally published as Erkenntnis und Interesse. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1968.)Google Scholar
[4] Habermas, J.A Postscript to Knowledge and Human Interests.Philosophy of the Social Sciences 3(1973): 157189.Google Scholar
[5] Habermas, J. Theory and Practice, (trans.) Viertel, J. Boston: Beacon Press, 1973. (Translation and abridgment of essays from the fourth edition of Theorie und Praxis Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1971, together with one essay “Labor and Interaction: Remarks on Hegel’s Jena Philosophy of Mind” from Technik und Wissenschaft als “Ideologie”. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1968.)Google Scholar
[6] McCarthy, T. The Critical Theory of Jürgen Habermas. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, 1978.Google Scholar
[7] Rorty, R.Epistemological Behaviorism and the De-Transcendentalization of Analytic Philosophy.” In Zur Zukunft der Transzendental Philosophie. (Neue Hefte für Philosophie. Heft. 14.) Edited by Rüdiger Bubner, et al. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1978. Pages 115–112.Google Scholar
[8] Sellars, W. Science, Perception, and Reality. New York: Humanities Press, 1963.Google Scholar
[9] Sellars, W.Counterfactuals, Dispositions, and the Causal Modalities.” In Concepts Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Volume II.) Edited by Feigl, H. et al. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1958. Pages 225308.Google Scholar