Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:07:51.429Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Grades of Organization and the Units of Selection Controversy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Robert C. Richardson*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Cincinnati, History and Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh

Extract

R. C. Lewontin (1970) proposed three criteria as jointly sufficient for a unit of evolutionary change and immediately went on to argue that selection could operate simultaneously at a variety of levels of organization. For natural selection to operate on a unit, there must be variation in the objects in question: natural selection “chooses” between alternatives, so there must be different alternatives. This variation must affect fitness: the variation available must create different probabilities of reproductive success. Third, this variation in fitness must be heritable: there must be a correlation between parents and offspring for the traits yielding variation in fitness. In brief, for there to be evolution by natural selection, there must be heritable variation in fitness.

Among the concerns that might be raised over Lewontin's formula, one is particularly important. It was clearly brought out by Williams (1966) and is emphasized by Elliott Sober (1981).

Type
Part VIII. Levels of Explanation in Biology
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I am indebted in many points to discussions with William Bechtel and William Wimsatt, and particularly to Richard Burian whose comments saved me from a number of mistakes. This work was supported by a grant from the National Endowment for Humanities and support from the Taft Committee at the University of Cincinnati.

References

Dawkins, Richard. (1976). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Hamilton, W.D. (1971). “Geometry for the Selfish Herd.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 31: 295311.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Levins, Richard. (1970). “Complex Systems.” In Towards a Theoretical Biology. Edited by Waddington, C.H.. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Pages 7388.Google Scholar
Lewontin, R.C. (1970). “The Units of Selection.” Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics 1: 118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pattee, H.H. (1970). “The Problem of Biological Hierarchy.” In Towards a Theoretical Biology. Edited by Waddington, C.H.. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press. Pages 117136.Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert. (1962). “The Architecture of Complexity.” Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society 106: 467482. (As reprinted in Simon (1981). Pages 192-229;)Google Scholar
Simon, Herbert. (1981). The Sciences of the Artificial. 2nd enlarged ed. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott. (1981). “Holism, Individualism, and the Units of Selection.” In PSA 1980 Volume Two. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and Giere, R.N.. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 93121.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott. (1982a). “Selection of and Selection for.” Comments on papers by G.C. Williams and Michael Wade, University of Chicago Conference on Persistent Issues in Evolutionary Theory, March 3-5.Google Scholar
Sober, Elliott. (1982b). “Reifying the Selfish Gene.” Delivered at a Colloquium on Philosophical and Methodological Issues in Evolutionary Biology, University of Cincinnati, April 9-10.Google Scholar
Trivers, Robert L. (1971). “The Evolution of Reciprocal Altruism.” The Quarterly Review of Biology 46: 3557.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wade, M. (1978). “A Critical Review of the Models of Group Selection.” Quarterly Review of Biology 53: 101114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, G.C. (1966). Adaptation and Natural Selection. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, E.O. (1971). The Insect Societies. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wilson, E.O. (1975). Socioblologv: The Hew Synthesis. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William. (1972). “Teleology and the Logical Structure of Function Statements.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 3: 180.Google Scholar
Wimsatt, William. (1974). “Complexity and Organization.” In PSA 1972. (Boston Studies in The Philosophy of Science, Volume XX.) Edited by Schaffner, K. and Cohen, R.S.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 6786.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William. (1980). “Reductionistic Research Strategies and Their Biases in the Units of Selection Controversy.” In Scientific Discovery, Volume 2: Historical and Scientific Case Studies. Edited by Nickles, T.. Dordrecht: Reidel. Pages 213259.10.1007/978-94-009-9015-9_13CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wimsatt, William. (1981). “Units of Selections and the Structure of the Multi-Level Genome.” In PSA 1980, Volume Two. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and Giere, R.N.. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association. Pages 122183.Google Scholar
Wynne-Edwards, V.C. (1963). “Intergroup Selection in the Evolution of Social Systems.” Nature 200: 623626. (As reprinted in Caplan, A. (ed.). The Sooiobiology Debate. New York: Harper & Row, 1978. Pages 181-190.)CrossRefGoogle Scholar