Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:02:38.850Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Fitness and Explanation

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Gregory Cooper*
Affiliation:
University of Minnesota
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

Sustained controversy over a philosophical issue is often times symptomatic of differing commitments at a more fundamental philosophical level. I will argue that two current debates over the foundations of the theory of natural selection are cases in point. Alexander Rosenberg, at times together with Mary Williams, challenges what is becoming received orthodoxy about the foundations of this theory. He argues that the currently popular propensity interpretation of fitness does not legitimize explanations in terms of natural selection, and that furthermore, the biological fields which typically study the ways in which selection pressures originate in the organism/environment complex are not in fact part of the theory of natural selection at all. His foils in the first case are Robert Brandon, John Beatty and Susan Mills;2 on the second issue he is engaged in debate with Elliott Sober.3 We will see that, although the controversies are ostensibly about the interpretation of fitness, the issues, at bottom, involve the nature of scientific explanation.

Type
Part VII. Biology
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1988

Footnotes

1

I would like to thank John Beatty and James Hawthorne for their many helpful comments on earlier versions of this manuscript.

References

Beatty, J. (1980). “Optimal-Design Models and the Strategy of Model Building in Evolutionary Biology.Philosophy of Science 47: 532561.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Beatty, J. (1981). “What’s Wrong with the Received View of Evolutionary Theory?PSA 1980, Volume 2, R. Giere and Asquith, P. (eds.). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 397426.Google Scholar
Beatty, J. (1987). “On Behalf of the Semantic View.Biology and Philosophy 2: 1723.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brandon, R. N. (1978). “Adaptation and Evolutionary Theory.Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 9: 181206.Google Scholar
Brandon, R. N. (1981). “A Structural Description of Evolutionary Theory.PSA 1980, Volume 2, R. Giere and Asquith, P. (eds.). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 427439.Google Scholar
Brandon, R. N. and Beatty, J. (1984). “The Propensity Interpretation of ‘Fitness’.Philosophy of Science 51: 342347.10.1086/289184CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1981). “Explanatory Unification.Philosophy of Science 48: 507531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1985). “Darwin’s Achievement.” in Rescher, N. (ed.), Reason and Rationality in Natural Science, University Press of America, pp. 127189.Google Scholar
Lloyd, E. A. (1984). “A Semantic Approach to the Structure of Population Genetics.Philosophy of Science 51: 242264.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, S. K. and Beatty, J. (1979). “The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness.Philosophy of Science 46: 263286.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, E. (1961). The Structure of Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1978). “The Supervenience of Biological Concepts.Philosophy of Science 45: 368386.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1982). “On the Propensity Definition of Fitness.Philosophy of Science 49: 268273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1983). “Fitness.The Journal of Philosophy LXXX: 457473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1985). The Structure of Biological Science. New York: Cambridge.10.1017/CBO9781139171724CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenberg, A. and Williams, M. B. (1986). “Fitness as Primitive and Propensity.Philosophy of Science 53: 412418.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1983). “Equilibrium Explanation.Philosophical Studies 43: 201210.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1984a). “Fact, Fiction, and Fitness: A Reply to Rosenberg.The Journal of Philosophy LXXXI: 372383.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1984b). The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, Mass.: Bradford/MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1987). “Does Fitness Fit the Facts? A Reply to Williams and Rosenberg’s Rejoinder.The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIV: 220223.Google Scholar
Thompson, P. (1983). “The Structure of Evolutionary Theory: A Semantic Approach.Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 14: 215229.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraasen, B. C. (1980). The Scientific Image. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Waters, K. C. (1986). “Natural Selection Without Survival of the Fittest.Biology and Philosophy 1: 207225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, M. B. (1970). “Deducing the Consequences of Evolution: A Mathematical Model.Journal of Theoretical Biology 29: 343385.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Williams, M. B. and Rosenberg, A. (1985). ““Fitness” in Fact and Fiction: A Rejoinder to Sober.The Journal of Philosophy LXXXII: 738748.Google Scholar