Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:07:00.405Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Dissonance and Consistency according to Shackle and Shafer

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  31 January 2023

Isaac Levi*
Affiliation:
Columbia University
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Extract

Core share and HTML view are not available for this content. However, as you have access to this content, a full PDF is available via the ‘Save PDF’ action button.

R.A.Fisher introduced the fiducial argument as a means for obtaining something from nothing. He thought that on some occasions it was legitimate to obtain a posterior probability distribution over a range of simple statistical hypotheses without commitment to a prior distribution [4].

H.Jeffreys thought he could tame Fisher by casting his argument in a Bayesian mold through a derivation of the fiducial posterior from a suitably constructed ignorance prior via Bayes’ theorem and conditionalization on the data of experimentation. According to Jeffreys, Fisher was using something to obtain something after all ([7],pp.381-383).

D.V.Lindley furthered the process of taming by specifying allegedly necessary and sufficient conditions for the consistency of fiducial reasoning in contexts of one parameter estimation with Bayesian requirements [14]. I. Hacking exploited Lindley’s result to supply his own ingenious method for taming Fisher([5],ch. 9).

T.Seidenfeld has recently demonstrated that Lindley’s conditions are insufficient for consistency and that reconstructions like Jeffreys’ or Hacking’s lead to contradiction ([15], PP. 721-727).

Type
Part XI. Statistical Evidence
Copyright
Copyright © 1981 Philosophy of Science Association

References

[1] Carter, C.F. and Ford, J.L. (eds.). Uncertainty and Expectation in Economics. Oxford: Blackwell, 1972.Google Scholar
[2] Dempster, A.P.Upper and Lower Probabilities Induced by a Multivalued Mapping.Annals of Mathematical Statistics 38(1967): 325339.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[3] Dempster, A.P.A Generalization of Bayesian Inference.Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series B 30(1969): 205247.Google Scholar
[4] Fisher, R.A.Inverse Probability.Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 26(1930): 528535.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[5] Hacking, I. Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1965.Google Scholar
[6] Hooker, C.A., Leach, J.J., McLennen, E.F. (eds.). Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory, Volume 1. (University of Western Ontario Series in The Philosophy of Science. Volume 13). Dordrecht: Reidel, 1978.Google Scholar
[7] Jeffreys, H. Theory of Probability. 3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961.Google Scholar
[8] Levi, I.On Potential Surprise.Ratio 7(1966): 107129.Google Scholar
[9] Levi, I. Gambling with Truth. New York: Knopf, 1967. Reprinted by MIT Press, 1973.Google Scholar
[10] Levi, I. “Potential Surprise in the Context of Inquiry.” In [1]. Pages 213236.Google Scholar
[11] Levi, I.On Indeterminate Probability.Journal of Philosophy 71(1974): 391418. Reprinted in [6] with addenda. Pages 233261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[12] Levi, I.Direct Inference.Journal of Philosophy 74(1977): 529.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[13] Levi, I. “Irrelevance.” In [6]. Pages 263273.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[14] Lindley, D.V.Fiducial Distributions and Bayes’ Theorem.Journal of the Royal Statistical Society Series B 20(1958): 102107.Google Scholar
[15] Seidenfeld, T.Direct Inference and Inverse Inference.Journal of Philosophy 75(1978): 709730.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
[16] Shackle, G.L.S.Expectations in Economics.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1949.Google Scholar
[17] Shafer, G. A Mathematical Theory of Evidence. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1975.Google Scholar
[18] Shafer, G.Two Theories of Probability.” In PSA 1978. Volume 2. Edited by Asquith, P.D. and Hacking, I. East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association, 1981. Pages 441465.Google Scholar