Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-p9bg8 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T19:10:17.239Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Common Knowledge and Games with Perfect Information

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Philip J. Reny*
Affiliation:
The University of Western Ontario

Extract

It is by now rather well understood that the notion of common knowledge (first introduced by Lewis (1969) and later formalized by Aumann (1976)) plays a central role in the theory of games. (An event E is common knowledge between two individuals, if each knows E, each knows the other knows E, etc…). Indeed, most justifications of Nash's (1951) equilibrium concept usually include (perhaps only implicitly) the assumption that it is common knowledge among the players that both the Nash equilibrium in question will be played by all and that all players are expected utility maximizers. (We shall henceforth call expected utility maximizers, “rational”.) We hope to illustrate in an informal manner that there is in fact a large class of extensive form games, in which each of which it is not possible for rationality to be common knowledge throughout the game.

Type
Part XI. Decision and Game Theory
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Aumann, R. (1976), “Agreeing to Disagree”, The Annals of Statistics 4: 12361239.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Basu, K. (1985), “Strategic Irrationality in Extensive Games”, mimeo, Institute for Advanced Studies, Princeton.Google Scholar
Bernheim, D. (1984), “Rationalizable Strategic Behavior”, Econometrica 52: 10071028.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, K.G. (1985), “Modelling Rational Players”, mimeo, London School of Economics and University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Kreps, D., Milgrom, P., Roberts, J. and Wilson, R. (1982), “Rational Cooperation in the Finitely Repeated Prisoner's Dilemma”, Journal of Economic Theory 27: 245252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kreps, D., and Wilson, R. (1982), “Sequential Equilibria”, Econometrica 50: 863894.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, D. (1969), Convention: A Philosophical Study. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Mertens, J.F., and Zamir, S. (1985), “Formulation of Bayesian Analysis for Games with Incomplete Information”, International Journal of Game Theory 14: 129.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nash, J. (1951), “Noncooperative Games”, Annals of Mathematics 54: 286295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pearce, D. (1984), “Rationalizable Strategic Behaviour and The Problem of Perfection”, Econometrica 52: 10081050.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reny, P.J. (1987), “Explicable Equilibria”, mimeo, Princeton University and the University of Western Ontario.Google Scholar
Reny, P.J. (1988), “Rationality, Common Knowledge and The Theory of Games”, Ph.D. Dissertation, Chapter 1, Princeton University.Google Scholar
Rosenthal, R.W. (1981), “Games of Perfect Information, Predatory Pricing and the Chain-Store Paradox”, Journal of Economic Theory 25: 92100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Selten, R. (1965), “Spieltheoretische Behandlungeines Oligopolmodells mit Nachfragetragheit”, Zeitschrift fur die Gesamte Straatiswissenschaft 121: 301324.Google Scholar
Selten, R. (1975), “Reexamination of the Perfectness Concept for Equilibrium Points in Extensive Games”, International Journal of Game Theory 4: 2555.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tan, T. and Werlang, S. (1985), “On Aumann's Notion of Common Knowledge - An Alternative Approach”, mimeo, University of Chicago Business School and Princeton University.Google Scholar