Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-7cvxr Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T18:54:14.477Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Ceteris Paribus Clauses and Causality in Economics

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Daniel M. Hausman*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin-Madison

Extract

Explicit or implicit ceteris paribus clauses are pervasive in economics. People do not always buy more of x when the price of x decreases. The generalization holds only “other things being equal” or ceteris paribus. Not everybody wants more wealth, but economists have held that the generalization holds, ceteris paribus. When government imposes price controls, shortages do not always arise, but, ceteris paribus, they do. Ceteris paribus clauses are common in other sciences, but I shall confine my remarks to economics.

Many have found such ceteris paribus clauses problematic. For they are vague, and they seem to insulate theories from empirical criticism and correction. When the observed phenomena are not as the theory predicted, one can (or so it has been alleged) always claim that other things were not “equal”, that there was some “disturbance” or “interference” and thus that the ceteris paribus condition was not met.

Type
Part X. Laws in the Social Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © 1989 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I would like to thank Harold Kincaid, James Woodward and members of the audience at the PSA meetings for some searching and helpful criticisms and suggestions.

References

Aumann, R. (1964), “Markets with a Continuum of Traders”, Econometrica 32: 3950.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bliss, C. (1975), Capital Theory and the Distribution of Income. Amsterdam: North-Holland.Google Scholar
Boland, L. (1981), “On the Futility of Criticizing the Neoclassical Maximization Hypothesis”, American Economic Review 73: 1031-36.Google Scholar
Caldwell, B. (1983), “The Neoclassical Maximization Hypothesis: Comment”, American Economic Review 75: 824-27.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1953a), “The Marshallian Demand Curve”, in Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 4799.Google Scholar
Friedman, M. (1953b), “The Methodology of Positive Economics”, in Essays in Positive Economics pp. 343.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. (1981), Capital, Profits, and Prices: An Essay in the Philosophy of Economics. New York: Columbia University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. (1984), “Causal Priority”, Nous 18: 261-79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hausman, D. (1986), “Causation and Experimentation”, American Philosophical Quarterly 23: 143-54.Google Scholar
Hicks, J. (1979), Causality in Economics. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Hutchison, T. (1938), The Significance and Basic Postulates of Economic Theory. rpt. New York: A. M. Kelley, 1960.Google Scholar
Lewis, D. (1973), “Causation”, Journal of Philosophy 70: 556-67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mackie, J. (1974), The Cement of the Universe. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Marshall, A. (1930), Principles of Economics. 8th ed. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Mill, J.S. (1836), “On the Definition of Political Economy and the Method of Investigation Proper to It”, rpt. in vol. 4 of Collected Works of John Stuart Mill. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1967.Google Scholar
Mill, J.S. (1843), A System of Logic. London: Longmans, Green and Co., 1949.Google Scholar
Mongin, P. (1986), “Are “All-and-Some” Statements Falsifiable After All? The Example of Utility Theory”, Economics and Philosophy 2: 185-95.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morgenbesser, S. (1956), “Theories and Schemata in the Social Sciences”, Dissertation, University of Pennsylvania.Google Scholar
Simon, H. (1953), “Causal Ordering and Identifiability”, rpt. in Models of Discovery and other Topics in the Methods of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, 1977, pp. 5380.Google Scholar
Stalnaker, R. (1972), “Pragmatics”, in Davidson, D. and Harman, G., eds. Semantics of Natural Language, Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 380-97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Yeager, L. (1969), “Methodenstreit over Demand Curves”, Journal of Political Economy 68: 5364.CrossRefGoogle Scholar