Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-lnqnp Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T17:32:29.819Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theory-ladenness of Perception Arguments

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Michael A. Bishop*
Affiliation:
Iowa State University

Extract

The theory-ladenness of perception argument is not an argument at all. It is two clusters of arguments. The first cluster is empirical. These arguments typically begin with a discussion of one or more of the following psychological phenomena: (a) the conceptual penetrability of the visual system, (b) voluntary perceptual reversal of ambiguous figures, (c) adaptation to distorting lenses, or (d) expectation effects. From this evidence, proponents of theory-ladenness typically conclude that perception is in some sense “laden” with theory. The second cluster attempts to extract deep epistemological lessons from this putative fact Some philosophers conclude that science is not (in any traditional sense) a rational activity (Feyerabend 1975); while others conclude that we must radically reconceptualize what scientific rationality involves (Kuhn 1970; Churchland 1979).

Type
Part VIII. Kuhnian Themes: SSR at Thirty
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

1

I would like to thank Paul Boghossian, Paul Churchland, Eric Gampel, Peter Godfrey-Smith, Patricia Kitcher, David Magnus, Joe Mendola, Sam Mitchell, Graham Nerlich, Stephen Stich and my colleagues at Iowa State University for very helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper. I owe special thanks to Philip Kitcher for guidance that invariably led in fruitful directions.

References

Bishop, M.A. (1991), “Why the Semantic Incommensurability Thesis is Self-Defeating”, Philosophical Studies 63: 343-356.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bruner, J.S., and Postman, L. (1949), “On the Perception of Incongruity: A Paradigm”, Journal of Personality 18: 206-223.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Churchland, P.M. (1979), Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, P.M. (1988), “Perceptual Plasticity and Theoretical Neutrality: A Reply to Jerry Fodor”, Philosophy of Science 55: p. 167-187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dolezal, H. (1982), Living in a World Transformed: Perceptual and Performatory Adaptation to Visual Distortion. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Feyerabend, P. (1975), Against Method. London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
Fodor, J. (1983), The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1984), “Observation Reconsidered”, Philosophy of Science 51: 23-43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gale, A.G. and Findlay, J.M. (1983), “Eye Movement Patterns in Viewing Ambiguous Figures”, in Groner (et. al.) Eye Movements and Psychological Functions: International Views. Hillsdale, New Jersey: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, pp. 145-168.Google Scholar
Kohler, I. (1964), “The Formation and Transformation of the Perceptual World”, Psychological Issues 3:1-173.Google Scholar
Kuhn, T.S., (1970), The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Taylor, J.G. (1962), The Behavioral Basis of Perception. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Warren, R. (1970), “Perceptual Restoration of Missing Speech Sounds”, Science 167: 392-3.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed