Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-fscjk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T18:40:25.994Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Realism and Methodological Change

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Jarrett Leplin*
Affiliation:
University of North Carolina, Greensboro

Extract

An effective way to challenge scientific realism these days is to ask whether evidence for a theory’s truth can ever outstrip evidence for its utility. Granted that we might have strong evidence of a theory’s explanatory, predictive, heuristic, and technological utility, might we have in addition evidence of its truth? A negative answer claims that all the evidence in support of a theory is, immediately, evidence of pragmatic virtues, and only indirectly, if at all, evidence of truth. Realism then reduces to a willingness to infer truth from utility. Evidently, none of the evidence by which theories are tested will pertain to this inference, so the only recourse for sustaining it is to a metalevel at which truth and utility are compared in the abstract. And there enormous problems loom.

Type
Part XI. Realism, Methodology and Underdetermination
Copyright
Copyright © 1992 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Barrow, J. (1991), Theories of Everything. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (1986), “Unnatural Attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist Attachments to Science”, Mind 95: 149-179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Frampton, P. and Bum-Hoon, L. (1990), “SU(15) Grand Unification”, Physical Review Letters, 64: 619-621.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, I. (1989), “Extragalactic Reality: The Case of Gravitational Lensing”, Philosophy of Science 56:555-582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, P. (1991), “On the Nature and Norms of Theoretical Commitment”, Philosophy of Science 58:1-15.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1981), “A Confutation of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science, 48:19-49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L (1986), “Methodology’s Prospects”, in PSA 1986, volume 2, Fine, A. and Machamer, P. (eds.). East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp.347-355.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1977), Progress and its Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984), Science and Values. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1989), “If it Ain’t Broke, Don’t Fix it”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 40: 369-376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. and Leplin, J. (1991), “Empirical equivalence and Underdetermination”, Journal of Philosophy, 88:449-473.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1986), “Methodological Realism and Scientific Rationality”, Philosophy of Science 53: 31-53.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Miller, R. (1987), Fact and Method. Princeton: Princeton University PressGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1988), “The Ultimate Argument for Scientific Realism”, in Relativism and Realism in Science, Nola, R. (ed.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, pp. 229-253.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Fraassen, B. (1989), Laws and Symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weinberg, S. (1981), “The Decay of the Proton”, Scientific American, 6/81. pp. 74 ff.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. (1988), “The Value of a Fixed Methodology”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 39: 263-275.CrossRefGoogle Scholar