Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:11:39.279Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Incredibility of Rejecting Belief-Desire-Action Explanations

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Alfred F. MacKay*
Affiliation:
Oberlin College

Extract

An argument of Donald Davidson's (1970, 1973) has convinced many people that there is something suspect about the commonsense, belief-desire-action explanations that most of us apply to human behavior. Alexander Rosenberg (1980, 1983) has been convinced by Davidson's argument, and uses its conclusion (together with some ideas about sociobiology) to explain what he regards as the persistent failures of the social sciences. In this paper I shall not comment directly upon Davidson's argument. Instead, I will discuss an unacceptable implication of Rosenberg's use of it. Whether this reflects on Davidson's argument I leave for others to decide.

This is how Rosenberg uses the conclusion of Davidson's argument to explain the (alleged) failures of economics.

Philosophers have shown that the terms in which ordinary thought and the behavioral sciences describe the cause and effects of human action do not describe “natural kinds,” : they do not divide nature at the joints.

Type
Part II. Economics as a Science
Copyright
Copyright © 1983 Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Austin, J.L. (1957). “A Plea For Excuses. ” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (New Series) 57: 1-30. (As reprinted in Philosophical Papers. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1961. Pages 123-152.Google Scholar
Davidson, D.D. (1970). “Mental Events.” In Experience and Theory. Edited by Foster, L. and Swanson, J.. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press. Pages.79-101.Google Scholar
Davidson, D.D. (1973). “The Material Mind.” In Logic. Methodology. and Philosophy of Science IV. (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics. Volume 74.) Edited by P. Suppes et al. Amsterdam: North Holland. Pages 709-722.Google Scholar
Donnellan, K. (1966). “Reference and Definite Descriptions.” The Philosophical Review 75: 281-304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Donnellan, K. (1968). “Putting Humpty Dumpty Together Again.” The Philosophical Review 77: 203-215.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gettier, E. (1963). “Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?” Analysis 23: 121-123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Grice, H.P. (1975). “Logic and Conversation.” In Syntax and Semantics. Volume 3. Edited by Cole, P. and Morgan, J.. New York: Academic Press. Pages 41-58.Google Scholar
MacKay, A.F. (1968). “Mr. Donnellan and Humpty Dumpty on Referring.” The Philosophical Review 77: 197-202.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1976). Microeconomic Laws. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1980). Sociobiology and the Preemption of Social Science. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1983). “If Economics Isn't Science, What Is It?” The Philosophical Forum 14: 296-314 .Google Scholar
van de Wetering, J. (1976). The Corpse on the Dike. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.Google Scholar