Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T06:03:57.629Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Explaining Scientific Discovery

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  28 February 2022

Noretta Koertge*
Affiliation:
Indiana University

Extract

The history of science provides two prima facie reasons for believing that there is a “logic” to scientific discovery. The first is the phenomenon of multiple or simultaneous discoveries. The second is the fact that internalist historians of science (who eschew non-cognitive explanations) routinely explain how a discovery was made and why scientist X took an important step which scientist Y did not!

However, some philosophers have argued that purported historical explanations of discovery are all sleight-of-hand tricks—what we really have is a confused mixture of rational reconstructions of the justification steps in the process combined with a description, not an explanation, of the creative leaps. Others would claim that historians do indeed help us to understand scientific discoveries, but the mode of understanding involved is not that provided by the Hempelian covering law model. Rather we empathize with the creative leaps of past geniuses.

Type
Part I. Discovery, Rationality and History of Science
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1982

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Agassi, Joseph. (1963). Towards an Historiography of Science. The Hague: Mouton and Co.Google Scholar
Boden, Margaret. (1977). Artificial Intelligence and Natural Man. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Finocchiaro, Maurice A. (1973). History of Science as Explanation. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
Gutting, Gary. (1980). “Science as Discovery.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie 34: 2648.Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl G. (1965). Aspects of Scientific Explanation. New York: The Free Press.Google Scholar
Hesse, Mary B. (1966). Models and Analogies in Science. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
Koertge, Noretta. (1975). “Popper's Metaphysical Research Program for the Human Sciences.” Inquiry 18: 437462.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry. (1977). Progress and Its Problems. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1979). “Review of History of Science as Explanation by Finocehiaro, M.A..” Erkenntnls 14: 93102.Google Scholar
Nickles, Thomas. (1981). “What is A Problem That We May Solve It.” Synthese 47: 85118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1957). The Poverty of Historicism. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1967). “La Rationalité et le Statut du Principe de Rationalité.” In Les Fondements Philosophiques des Systèmes Economiaues. Edited by Classen, E.M.. Paris: Payot. Pages 142150.Google Scholar
Popper, Karl R. (1972). Objective Knowledge. London: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley E. (1966). The Foundations of Scientific Inference. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley E. (1970a). “Bayes's Theorem and the History of Science.” In Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science. (Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Volume V.) Edited by Stuewer, Roger. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, Wesley E. (1970b). Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar