Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-01T11:53:27.289Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A LESSON IN EVENTFUL TEMPORALITY: PEDAGOGIES OF DONALD TRUMP FROM ABROAD

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  04 February 2020

Thomas Jessen Adams*
Affiliation:
University of Sydney, Australia
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Type
Spotlight: Teaching US Politics in the Age of Trump: International Perspectives
Copyright
Copyright © American Political Science Association 2020 

An unexpected consequence of Donald Trump’s presidency has been its occurrence exposing popular simplifications of American history and politics. Trump’s election and presidency has had the salutary effect of sharpening some of the contradictions of American political analysis. Methodological orientations, epistemologies, and just-so thinking that were taken for granted—in scholarship and in popular thought—have been exposed for their deep decontextualization and simplification.

I began teaching US history and politics in Australia in 2014 after 10 years in diverse American university contexts. Beyond important institutional contrasts, the key difference between American and Australian students is native contextual knowledge. This, of course, is standard for anyone teaching geographically contingent topics outside of the subject country.Footnote 1 We cannot assume that students have some knowledge of things we often take as given when walking into an American classroom. Things as diverse as rights-based constitutionalism and basic geographic characteristics cannot be assumed. American federalism and local governance are often particularly alien. For instance, a lecture on the politics and history of school segregation must attend to foreign notions of municipal control of education. Students also are less embedded in ongoing ideological debates within American culture—especially social media—about the meaning of Trump. Finally, whereas Australian students occasionally exhibit stereotypes of the United States and Americans, in most instances, they are so self-evidently shallow (e.g., all Americans own guns) as to be easily disabused and, in my experience, less ingrained than stereotypes of Americans vis-à-vis other Americans.

These contexts precede the manner in which students and the broader public at large in Australia understand American political life. The scale of global surprise that greeted Trump’s election rivaled that of most Americans. Indeed, given that outlets like the New York Times and fivethirtyeight.com probably disproportionately inform the opinions of non-Americans and local media outside of the United States, it is quite possible the disbelief surpassed that experienced in American living rooms on November 8, 2016. I spent much of that night doing interviews with Australian media, the subject of which was some variation of “How could (most) everyone have gotten this so wrong?”

Continued surprise also has been the hallmark of how Trump appears in my classroom. His presidency is an event that requires explanation—for students, the general public, and scholars alike. An event that many were unable to conceive of before the fact and are baffled by after the fact. I emphasize event because sophisticated thinking about events, what Sewell (Reference Sewell2005) termed “eventful temporality,” is a hallmark of theoretically conscious historical epistemology and what separates it from its positivistic/experimental and teleological/path-dependent social-scientific cousins. Eventful temporality disavows the notion intrinsic to experimental/positivistic social science that causality and its measurement can be fixed across time and place and that any occurrence can be isolated from its context. Although I agree with teleology/path dependency insofar as arguing that prior events affect those in the future, eventful temporality denies that causality and its structures can be uniform across time and space (Sewell Reference Sewell2005). This framework is not limited to the discipline of history but rather is found across divisions of human knowledge. It is an epistemological point, not a disciplinary one—a point that Trump’s presidency usefully demonstrates in the classroom.

When students bring less fixed knowledge of American life to the classroom, it is precisely the unfathomability of Trump that makes him pedagogically useful. The broad popular explanations for Trump’s election typically involve some prioritization of one of the following abstractions: so-called racial resentment; sexism and misogyny; populism defined as mood/status anxiety (Jäger Reference Jäger2019)Footnote 2; anti-Muslim/Latin American nativism; non-voting; James Comey’s actions; Russian interference; third-party voting; supposed white working-class conservatism; the reemergence of Theodor Adorno’s authoritarian personality; voter suppression; deindustrialization, or automation and capital flight. Through encounters with scholarship or media, students bring these explanations into the classroom. Unembedded in ongoing popular debates within American life, however, they are less ideologically wedded to specific explanations for Trump.

This is not to advance or critique any of the previous interpretations but rather to suggest that each as an explanation for an event like Trump’s election/presidency begs more questions than they answer. This opens up a broad pedagogical space to study a wide swath of radically different temporal events in American political life—from centuries of American exceptionalist ideology to the forces behind deindustrialization; from the strategies of modern voter suppression to the broad diversity of reasons more Americans see no reason to vote than vote for any single candidate. Accounting for the existence of one of these interpretations requires a contingent and temporally heterogeneous explanation. Accounting for the event of Trump’s presidency in any halfway convincing manner then requires a sophisticated attention to countless other events and processes of radically distinct temporalities.

Less embedded in American popular and social media discourse, Australian students grasp this intuitively. To understand the existence of something like “racial resentment” as a motivating factor for a political decision, they then immediately want to know when, why, in what context, and for whom does this catch-all concept become motivating? In student discussion, I have rarely seen recourse to the phenomenon as pathological—for instance, built into American cultural “DNA”—that often becomes the explanation in US contexts. Rather, which policies, cultural trends, or political strategies led a certain group to act on this in this specific time and place? If some cohorts of Americans tend to exhibit characteristics of “racial resentment” or nativism, why do some act on it in politically meaningful ways and others do not? Why do some people exhibit these characteristics one day in the voting booth and show solidarity in the workplace the next? The very existence of so many distinct interpretive strands for this singular event and the clear way in which these strands are themselves temporally eventful tends to disabuse students of the more monocausal explanations such as Comey’s actions. Students quickly default to a preference for overdetermination in the face of just-so narratives, ranging from Russian interference to the almost neurological existence of something like an authoritarian personality.

As an epistemological strategy, the beneficence of temporal eventfulness is most clear in relationship to recognizably big events. An explanation for those events built on radically heterogeneous temporalities clearly “trumps” those that imagine path dependency or positivist certainty as meaningful explanations for social phenomena when the stakes are raised. Such a standpoint can filter down to events that are less prima facie world historic. Why imagine that an event like Trump’s election functions any different than any other event? In this way, the global surprise that greeted Trump’s rise provides an object lesson in eventful temporality, a pedagogical “silver lining” for those of us trying to help students across the globe make compelling interpretations of their world.

Footnotes

1. For an exploration of this in relationship to broader intellectual and research culture, see Adams and Gleeson-White (Reference Adams and Gleeson-White2018).

2. For an excellent recent discussion of history of “populism” as a term and its relationship to status anxiety and Cold War social science, see Jäger (Reference Jäger2019).

References

REFERENCES

Adams, Thomas Jessen, and Gleeson-White, Sarah. 2018. “American Cultures: The View from the Pacific.” Journal of American Studies 52 (3): 589–92.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jäger, Anton. 2019. “The Masses Against the Classes, or, How to Talk About Populism Without Talking About Class.” Nonsite.Org 28 (May).Google Scholar
Sewell, William H. Jr. 2005. Logics of History: Social Theory and Social Transformation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar