Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-09T22:50:36.509Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Creationism, Evolution and the Courts

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  02 September 2013

Karen O'Connor
Affiliation:
Emory University
Gregg Ivers
Affiliation:
Emory University

Extract

The separation of religion and state is a fundamental principle of American constitutional democracy, but agreement over the proper relationship between God and Caesar is a far from settled matter. The concern of the framers of the Constitution for religious freedom is reflected in the First Amendment, which prohibits Congress from making laws respecting the establishment of religion or restricting the free exercise of religious beliefs. The language employed is enigmatic, reflecting the delicate balance that the Constitution seeks to strike among the individual, the state and religion. The mosaic of religious groups in colonial America and the concern by the Founders to protect their religious freedom was “one of the forces that ultimately led to the adoption of a secular Constitution that included specific mention of free exercise and disestablishment” (Pfeffer, 1977: 13).

As the branch of government whose responsibility it is to decide the constitutionality of federal and state laws that challenge the relationship between religion and the state, the judiciary is faced with the unenviable task of adjudicating disputes that fall within the language of the First Amendment. Since the 1940s, when it first began applying the religion clauses to the states, the Court has ruled on the constitutionality of prayer and Bible reading in public schools, government assistance to parochial schools as well as general issues of what the state may legitimately demand from an individual without impinging on the free exercise of his or her religious beliefs. The aim of the Court has been to strike a balance between respect for the role of religion in American public life while prohibiting state preference for any religious faith. It is hardly surprising, then, that the fruits of its labors have been greeted with less than unanimous satisfaction from the competing interests of religious and non-religious groups. To expect anything more would be to discount the complex question of what limits the Constitution places on religion as a moral and educational component in our public and social order.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The American Political Science Association 1988

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Edwards v. Aguillard. 1987. 107 S.Ct. 2573.10.2307/3971285CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Epperson v. Arkansas. 1968. 398 U.S. 97.Google Scholar
Lemon v. Kurtzman. 1971. 403 U.S. 602.Google Scholar
McIntosh, Wayne V. 1985. Litigating Scientific Creationism, or ‘Scopes’ II, III…. Law & Policy 7: 375394.10.1111/j.1467-9930.1985.tb00358.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mozert v. Hawkins County Public Schools. 1987. 647 Fed. Supp. 1194. 6th Circuit.Google Scholar
Pfeffer, Leo. 1977. Religious Freedom. Skokie, IL: National Textbook Company.Google Scholar
Smith v. Board of School Commissioners, Mobile County, Alabama.Google Scholar