Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gxg78 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T10:44:51.634Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Perverse Reasons

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 February 2021

Abstract

For an agent to be motivated by a normatively perverse reason is to be motivated by a normative or evaluative thought as such which, if true, would count as such against the action that it motivates the agent to perform, or against the attitude that it motivates the agent to take. For example, that an action is morally wrong or prudentially bad counts, as such, against performing the action. When the thought that an action is morally wrong or prudentially bad (bad for me) motivates me as such to perform the action, my motivating reason is normatively perverse. If being motivated by normatively perverse reasons is possible, then what, if anything, is wrong about it? I present and reject some accounts of what may be wrong about normative perversity (wrong reasons, malfunctioning attitudes, practical irrationality, instability, evaluative ignorance). In the course of this discussion some desiderata emerge. Then I defend the suggestion that normative perversion is socially undesirable, in that it undermines certain valuable interpersonal and intrapersonal relations. Entering and maintaining these relations is constitutive of valuing people as beings to whom reasonable justification is owed. I show how this account satisfies the desiderata.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Alvarez, Maria, ‘Reasons for Action: Justification, Motivation, Explanation’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/reasons-just-vs-expl/>..>Google Scholar
Augustine, Confessions (II edition), edited by Foley, M. P. (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett, 2006).Google Scholar
Gregory, Alex, ‘The Guise of Reasons’, American Philosophical Quarterly, 50 (2013), 6372.Google Scholar
Hanisch, Christoph (ed.), Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 21. Special Issue on ‘Acting Under the Guise of the Bad’ (2018).10.1007/s10677-017-9849-3CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawkins, Jennifer, ‘Desiring the bad under the guise of the good’, Philosophical Quarterly, 58 (2008), 244–64.10.1111/j.1467-9213.2007.520.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hawthorne, John and Magidor, Ofra, ‘Reflections on the Ideology of Reasons’ in Star, Daniel (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Reasons and Normativity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018).Google Scholar
Howard, Christopher, ‘Fittingness’, Philosophy Compass 13 (2018), e12542.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2000).Google Scholar
Jacobson, Daniel, ‘Fitting Attitude Theories of Value’, The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition), Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/fitting-attitude-theories/>..>Google Scholar
Kant, Immanuel, Religion Within the Bounds of Bare Reason (Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett, 2009).Google Scholar
Lord, Errol, The Importance of Being Rational (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2018).10.1093/oso/9780198815099.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McHugh, Conor and Way, Jonathan, ‘Against the Taking Condition’, Philosophical Issues, 26 (2016), 314–31.10.1111/phis.12074CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McHugh, Conor and Way, Jonathan, ‘What is Reasoning?’, Mind, 127 (2018), 167–96.10.1093/mind/fzw068CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pettit, Philip and Smith, Michael, ‘Practical Unreason’, Mind, 102 (1993), 5379.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rabinowicz, Wlodek and Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni, ‘The strike of the demon: On fitting pro-attitudes and value’, Ethics, 114 (2004), 391423.10.1086/381694CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Raz, Joseph, ‘The Guise of the Bad’, Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy, 10 (2016), 115.10.26556/jesp.v10i3.102CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ridge, Michael, Impassioned Belief (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199682669.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rowland, Richard, The Normative and the Evaluative: The Buck-Passing Account of Value (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2019).10.1093/oso/9780198833611.001.0001CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scanlon, T. M., What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1998).Google Scholar
Schlosser, Markus E., ‘Taking Something as a Reason for Action’, Philosophical Papers, 41 (2012), 267304.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Setiya, Kieran, ‘Sympathy for the devil’ in Tenenbaum, Sergio (ed.), Desire, Practical Reason, and the Good (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010), 82110.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, Michael, The Moral Problem (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994).Google Scholar
Stocker, Michael, ‘Desiring the bad: An essay in moral psychology’, Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1979), 738–53.10.2307/2025856CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stratton-Lake, Philip and Hooker, Brad, ‘Scanlon versus Moore on goodness’ in Horgan, Terry and Timmons, Mark (eds.), Metaethics After Moore (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).Google Scholar
Suikkanen, Jussi, ‘Buck-passing accounts of value’, Philosophy Compass, 4 (2009), 768–79.10.1111/j.1747-9991.2009.00253.xCrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sussman, David, ‘For Badness’ Sake’, Journal of Philosophy, 106 (2009), 613–28.10.5840/jphil20091061129CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, Sergio, Appearances of the Good: An Essay on the Nature of Practical Reason (Cambridge University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Tenenbaum, Sergio, ‘The Guise of the Guise of the Bad’, Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 21 (2018), 520.10.1007/s10677-017-9855-5CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, David, ‘The Guise of the Good’, Noûs, 26 (1992), 326.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, Bernard, ‘Internal and External Reasons’ in Moral Luck (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), 101113.10.1017/CBO9781139165860.009CrossRefGoogle Scholar