Article contents
Patience and Courage
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 30 January 2009
Extract
Suppose your friends had to ascribe a single vice to you in large measure, along with any virtues that could be coherently combined with that salient vice. Suppose further that the vice had to be either cowardice or impatience. Which would you choose?
I believe almost everyone would choose impatience without hesitation. There are sound moral as well as purely self-regarding reasons for despising cowardice, and to that extent our preference would be reasonable. If we say that a man who is a coward is also compassionate, we know that his compassion cannot be relied upon in any circumstances where it must contend with fear, and if he has a sense of justice, that will be useless if oppression has to be resisted. We cannot even expect him to pursue his own good whenever he perceives that to be hazardous, and so even the self-regarding virtues are corrupted by his dominating vice. On the other hand, a pronounced impatience may seem to be compossible with abundant virtue. Those who are just but cannot patiently endure tyranny are perhaps the most formidable threat to tyranny, and people who boldly go out to seize their own good often fare rather better than those who patiently await its arrival.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1993
References
1 Lovibond, Sabina, Realism and Imagination in Ethics (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983), 199Google Scholar; Cf. Murdoch, Iris, The Sovereignty of Good (London: Routledge, 1970), 53.Google Scholar
2 Sidgwick, Henry, The Methods of Ethics, 7th ed. (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1981), 332.Google Scholar
3 E.g., Weil, Simone, Gravity and Grace, (London: Routledge, 1952), 105.Google Scholar
4 Michael, 152–158.Google Scholar
5 Ibid., 466.
6 Trilling, Lionel, Sincerity and Authenticity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1978), 93.Google Scholar
7 Michael, 448–450.Google Scholar
8 Phillips, D. Z., Through a Darkening Glass (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 1982), 102.Google Scholar
9 Kundera, Milan, Life Is Elsewhere, trans, by Kuzzi, Peter (New York: Knopf, 1974), 78.Google Scholar
10 James, William, The Varieties of Religious Experience (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985), 219–220.Google Scholar
11 Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg, ‘The Two Faces of Courage’, and ‘Virtues and Their Vicissitudes’ in Mind in Action (Boston: Beacon Press, 1988), 399–329Google Scholar; and Rorty, Amélie Oksenberg, ‘The Advantages of Moral Diversity’, Social Philosophy & Policy, 9, no. 2 (1992): 38–62.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
12 Rorty, , ‘Virtues and Their Vicissitudes, 316–317.Google Scholar
13 Rorty, , ‘The Two Faces of Courage’, 308–310Google Scholar; ‘Virtues and Their Vicissitudes’, 318–324.Google Scholar
14 Rorty, , ‘The Two Faces of Courage’, 301–302.Google Scholar
15 Rorty, , ‘The Advantages of Moral Diversity’, 38–62.Google Scholar
16 Rorty, , ‘Virtues and Their Vicissitudes’, 323.Google Scholar
17 Geach, Peter, The Virtues (Cambridge University Press, 1977), 151.Google Scholar Geach is quoting Chesterton, though he does not tell us where Chesterton said this.
18 Levi, Primo, If Not Now, When? trans. by Weaver, William (London: Michael Joseph, 1986), 140–141.Google ScholarPubMed
19 Auden, W. H., ‘Anger’ in Angus Wilson et al., The Seven Deadly Sins (New York: William Morow, n.d.), 84–85.Google Scholar
20 I am very grateful to Margret Buchman and Pat White for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this paper.
- 17
- Cited by