Article contents
Justice
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 25 February 2009
Extract
Justice has always been regarded as one of the fundamental political virtues. No association of human individuals could subsist, says Hume, “were no regard paid to the laws of equity and justice”, and nearly every thinker who has turned to consider human society, has reached the same conclusion. Yet we are not at all clear what justice is, nor why it is so important. There are many other ideals which a society may cherish, and often reformers have felt impatient of having to compromise their aims merely for the sake of justice, and have not seen why the claims of justice should in any way override other political goods. I shall try to show why justice is, along with liberty, a peculiarly fundamental ideal, which is not merely co-ordinate with other ideals a society may value; but also that this notwithstanding, considerations of justice are not all-sufficient, and do not, and should not, always override all other political ideals.
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1972
References
1 Hume, David, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. Selby-Bigge, L. A., Oxford, 1902, 165 p. 206.Google Scholar
2 Republic VIII 558C5–6.Google Scholar
3 Gorgias 508a5–7.Google Scholar
4 Sweet, v. Parsley, , All England Law Reports, 1969, I, pp. 347–64.Google Scholar
5 Hart, H. L. A., “Bentham”, Proceedings of the British Academy, vol. XLVHI, 1962, pp. 316–17.Google Scholar
6 “Or Else”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. LXIX, 1969, pp. 219–22.Google Scholar
7 Confessions XI, c.xiii, 16.Google Scholar
8 St, Augustine, de Civitate Dei, Bk. XIX, c. 24.Google Scholar
9 Inst. Book I, Cap. 1.
10 Republic I 331 C3Google Scholar, “to give back anything one has received from any one”; to be accurate, I should add that this is only half of Simonides' definition, which starts by specifying truthfulness—so that what is being denned is as much honesty as justice.
11 Republic IV 433 b. 4Google Scholar, “to mind one's own business”.
12 Summa Theologica Q. LVIII, ast. 1.
13 See Lucas, J. R., “Or Else”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, vol. CXIX, 1968–1969.Google Scholar
14 Nicomachean Ethics V. 3.Google Scholar
15 Politics, III, 12.Google Scholar
16 de Jouvenel, Bertrand, Sovereignty, tr. Huntington, J. F., Cambridge, 1957, ch. 9, esp. pp. 164–5.Google Scholar
17 Distributive Justice, Indianapolis, 1966, esp. Ch. III, 9, Ch. IV, 1, 9.Google Scholar
18 Nicomachean Ethics, V. 4–5.Google Scholar
19 Republic II, 358.Google Scholar
20 See, e.g., Rapoport, Anatol, Fights, Games and Debates, Ann Arbor, 1960.Google Scholar
21 Vlastos, G., “Justice and Equality”, in R. B. Brandt, Social Justice, Englewood Cliffs, N. J., 1962, pp. 41.Google Scholar
22 Nicomachean Ethics, V. 11, 3; 1138a12.Google Scholar
23 Cambridge, 1955.
24 Rawls, John, “Justice as Fairness”, Philosophical Review, 67, 1958, pp. 164–94CrossRefGoogle Scholar reprinted in Laslett, Peter and Runciman, W. G., eds., Philosophy, Politics and Society, Second Series, Oxford, 1962, pp. 132–57.Google Scholar
25 See Rapoport, Anatol, Fights, Games and Debates, Ann Arbor, 1960, Ch. X, pp. 173–7Google Scholar
26 But see Raiffa, H. “Arbitration Schemes for Generalised two-person Games” in Ruhn, H. W. and Tucker, A. W., eds., Contributions to the Theory of Games, Princeton, 1953Google Scholar (summarised in Rapoport, , pp. 193–4).Google Scholar
27 Schelling, T. C., The Strategy of Conflict, Cambridge, Mass., 1960, Chs. 3, 4, pp. 53–118.Google Scholar
28 Hayek, F. A., “The Principles of a Liberal Social Order”, in Studies in Philosophy, Politics and Economics, London, 1967, pp. 160–77.Google Scholar
29 Lucas, J. R., Principles of Politics, Oxford, 1966, § 67.Google Scholar
30 Barry, Brian, “Social Justice”, The Oxford Review, 5, 1967, § 7, p. 49.Google Scholar
31 See Lucas, J. R., Principles of Politics, Oxford, 1966, §§ 17, 8; pp. 68–72, 31–4.Google Scholar
32 p. 52.
- 12
- Cited by