Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rcrh6 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T15:20:20.227Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Idealism and Religion in the Philosophy of T.L.S. Sprigge

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  15 September 2010

Brenda Almond*
Affiliation:
University of Hull

Abstract

Although T.L.S. Sprigge described idealist philosophy as the stage beyond religion, his pantheistic idealism, while not itself a religion, offers a conception of God that seeks to meet the aspiration of human beings to understand their own place in the universe. While he shared with most mid twentieth century British philosophers a basic assumption of the primacy of experience, Sprigge took this strong empiricist assumption in a Berkeleyian rather than a Humean direction. This enabled him to find a place for the phenomenon of religious consciousness, which he saw as the source of a yearning that can be met by absolute idealism's conception of a ‘Whole’ that encompasses ourselves and all aspects of our world. He describes this recognition as the faltering adumbration of a truth – one that is sometimes encountered in aesthetic experience, and sometimes more directly in the lives of mystics. The metaphysical basis for this form of absolute idealism is provided by a concept of time in which each fleeting ‘now’ has a fixed and permanent place, and by a theory of identity according to which personal individuality is dissolved in a unitary ‘Whole’.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 2010

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 Gale, R.M., ‘Timothy Sprigge: the Grinch that stole time’, in Basile, Pierfrancesco and McHenry, Leemon B. (eds.) Consciousness, Reality and Value, (Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag, 2007), 2740Google Scholar, 27.

2 T.L.S. Sprigge, ‘Orientations’, Philosophical Writings, 2, (May, 1996), 1–3.

3 Pascal, Blaise, Pensées (Oxford: Oxford World's Classics, trans. Levi, Honor, (ed.) Levi, Anthony, 2008), 172Google Scholar.

4 Pascal op. cit. note 3, 26.

5 Ibid. 153.

6 Sprigge, T.L.S., The God of Metaphysics (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2006), 191CrossRefGoogle Scholar.

7 Sprigge, T.L.S., Theories of Existence (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1984), 72Google Scholar.

8 T.H. Green, Collected Works, iii., 146, cited Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 153.

9 Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 225.

10 Ibid. 226.

11 Ibid. 261.

12 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 75–76.

13 Basile and McHenry, Op. cit. note 1, 320.

14 William Sweet, ‘God, Sprigge, and Idealist Philosophy of Religion’ in Basile and McHenry, Op. cit. note 1, 181–210.

15 Ibid. 182.

16 Ibid. 187.

17 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 157.

18 Leslie Armour, ‘Idealism and God’ in Basile and McHenry, Op. cit. note 1, 154. Armour argues that the key figure in the progression that brought idealism close to the heart of Christianity was Malebranche, because, while not denying the reality of material objects, he thought they were expressions of ideas in God's mind.

19 James, WilliamThe Varieties of Religious Experience (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1982 [1902]), 27Google Scholar.

20 Op. cit. note 3, 35. cp. his much-quoted dictum that ‘The heart has its reasons which reason itself does not know.’ Ibid. 158.

21 Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 540.

22 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 87.

23 Ibid. 174.

24 Ibid. 75.

25 Santayana, George, The Life of Reason, bk. 2. Reason in Society (London: Constable, 1905) 34Google Scholar.

26 Sprigge, T.L.S., The Vindication of Absolute Idealism (Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 1983), 253Google Scholar. Cited by McHenry Basile and McHenry, in Op. cit. note 1, 18.

27 T.L.S. Sprigge, ‘Absolute Idealism’ paper read to meeting of a Philosophical Society of England study group, Ringmer, Sussex, 9th Nov. 2005.

28 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 175.

29 I am grateful to Anthony O'Hear for suggesting this interpretation.

30 Pauline Phemister, ‘A Leibnizian God of Metaphysics?’ in Basile and McHenry, Op. cit. note 1, 211–27. 215.

31 Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 415.

32 Ford, Marcus P., ‘God and Evil: a Process Perspective’ in Basile and McHenry, Op. cit. note 1, 230–43. 238.

33 Leemon McHenry, ‘The philosophical idealism of Timothy Sprigge’, in Basile and McHenry, Op. cit. note 3, 17.

34 The full version of this much echoed saying of Empedokles of Akragas (fl. 444 B.C.) is as follows: ‘For it cannot be that aught can arise from what in no way is, and it is impossible and unheard of that what is should perish; for it will always be, wherever one may keep putting it.’ R.P. 165 a. in Burnet, J., Early Greek Philosophy (London: Adam & Charles Black, 1952 [1892]Google Scholar). See Lucretius (c.95–c.54 BC), De Rerum Natura, Book I, 162–226, for a description by a later Roman writer of ancient Greek atomism.

35 Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 260–61.

36 See Sprigge's review of two biographies of Spinoza, Within Reason: a life of Spinoza by Margaret Gullan-Whur and of Spinoza: A Life, by Steven Nadler. International Philosophical Quarterly vol XLI, No. 1, Issue No. 161, March 2001, 91–97.

37 Nadler, Steven, Spinoza: A Life (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999) 139CrossRefGoogle Scholar. Cited by Sprigge in review, Op. cit. note 36.

38 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 100.

39 Ibid. 106.

40 Hegel, , Early Theological Writings, trans. Knox, T.M. (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1948) 247Google Scholar.

41 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 112.

42 Ibid. 75–76.

43 Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 71.

44 Almond, Brenda, The Philosophical Quest (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1988), 185Google Scholar.

45 Sprigge, Theories of Existence, 154.

46 The full passage from Hume is this: ‘Where am I, or what? From what causes do I derive my existence, and to what condition shall I return? … I am confounded with all these questions, and begin to fancy myself in the most deplorable condition imaginable, inviron'd with the deepest darkness, and utterly deprive'd of the use of every member and faculty.

Most fortunately it happens, that since reason is incapable of dispelling these clouds, nature herself suffices to that purpose, and cures me of this philosophical melancholy and delirium, either by relaxing this bent of mind, or by some avocation, and lively impression of my senses, which obliterate all these chimeras. I dine, I play a game of backgammon, I converse, and am merry with my friends; and when, after three or four hours' amusement, I wou'd return to these speculations, they appear so cold, and strain'd, and ridiculous, that I cannot find in my heart to enter into them any farther.

Here, then I find myself absolutely and necessarily determi'd to live, and talk, and act like other people in the common affairs of life.’ Hume, David, A Treatise of Human Nature, Bk. I, 4. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1985 [1739–1740]), 316.Google Scholar

47 Sprigge, The God of Metaphysics, 191.