Hostname: page-component-7bb8b95d7b-lvwk9 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-10-07T06:32:38.289Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Getting Around Language

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Richard Mason
Affiliation:
Wolfson College, Cambridge

Extract

(i) Heraclitus wrote that human nature does not have right understanding, but divine nature does. The goddess of Parmenides tells us the Truth: that what exists is whole, single, undivided. We say (‘in our language’) that things are separably nameable and describable. That is incorrect. So ‘our’ use of language embodies error. In the Cratylus, Socrates says that the gods call things by names that are naturally right.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 ēthos gar anthrōpeion men ouk echei gnōmas, theion de echei, Diels-Kranz Fr. 78.Google Scholar

2 391de.

3 sicut scit materialia immaterialiter, et composita simpliciter, ita scit enuntiabilia non per modum enuntiabilium, quasi scilicet in intellectu ejus sit contpositio et divisio enuntiabilium; sed unumquodque cognoscit per simplicem intelligentiam, intelligendo essentiam uniuscujusque, Summa Theologiae la, 14, 14.Google Scholar

4 Michael, Luntley, Reason, Truth and Self (London: Routledge, 1995), p. 48.Google Scholar

5 This must be the argument of Graham, Priest'sBeyond the Limits of Thought (Cambridge University Press, 1995).Google Scholar

6 to gar auto noein estin te kai einai, Diels-Kranz 3.Google Scholar

7 ‘On Saying That’, Inquiries into Truth and Interpretation (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984).Google Scholar

8 In Moore, G. E.Philosophical Papers (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1959).Google Scholar

9 This is the history narrated in Ian, Hacking, Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? (Cambridge University Press, 1975)Google Scholar and more famously, but less plainly, in Richard, Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton University Press, 1979).Google Scholar

10 Bernard, Williams, Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1978), p. 65.Google Scholar

11 non … quod Deus sit omnipotens, sed Credo in Deum omnipotentem, Summa Theologiae IIaIIae. 1,2.Google Scholar

12 T. C. O'Brian (ed.) (London: Eyre and Spottiswoode, 1974) vol. 31, p. 13, note k.Google Scholar

13 Questiones Disputatce de Veritate, IX, 4, trs Mulligan, R. W. (Chicago: Regnery, 1952), vol. 1, pp. 422, 426.Google Scholar

14 Wittgenstein, , Notebooks 1914-1916, trs Anscombe, G. E. M. (Oxford: Blackwell 1961), p. 67e (20 June 1915).Google Scholar

15 ‘Realism and Anti-Realism’, p. 465 and ‘Realism’, p. 230, both in The Seas of Language (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1993).Google Scholar

16 ‘Common Sense and Physics’, The Seas of Language, p. 378.Google Scholar

17 Summa Theologies Ia. 2, 1.Google Scholar

18 Frege: Philosophy of Language (London: Duckworth, 1st edn, 1973), pp. 118120.Google Scholar

19 Finnegans Wake (London: Faber and Faber, 1975 edn.) p. 149.Google Scholar