Article contents
Doubts about Prima Facie Duties
Published online by Cambridge University Press: 25 February 2009
Extract
Sir David Ross introduced and discussed his notion of prima facie duties in chapter 2 of The Right and the Good, and it is to this chapter that I shall devote most attention. I wish to show that the distinction between prima facie and “actual” duties, as expounded by Ross, entails that there are no “actual” duties; and I wish to show that this unfortunate consequence of the distinction arises from Ross's explicit epist-emological views. Writers such as Ewing, Baier and Frankena, who have quoted Ross's distinction with some degree of approval, force one to ask how, precisely, they interpreted it. In the first part of this paper I set out Ross's exposition in detail, since failure to do this has blinded adherents to its difficulties; in the second part I summarise my findings and indicate the problems Ross rightly poses for us; in the third part I suggest possible sources for Ross's views. Two points should be noted at the outset. Firstly, the distinction applies to acts, not actions; “act” refers to “the thing done, the initiation of change, and ‘action’ (to) the doing of it, the initiating of change, from a certain motive” (p. 7). Secondly, the term “right” is used throughout as synonymous with “what is my duty” (p. 6).
- Type
- Articles
- Information
- Copyright
- Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1970
References
1 Ross, W. D., The Right and the Good (London, 1930).Google Scholar
2 This paper was first read in the University of Edinburgh, 1964.
3 Strawson, P. F., “Ethical Intuitionism”, Philosophy, XXIV (1949).Google Scholar
4 See now Chopra, Y. N., “The Consequences of Human Actions”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXV (1964–1965).Google Scholar
5 Leibniz, G. W., New Essays on the Human Understanding (1704), Bk. III, ch. 3, para 6.Google Scholar
6 See now Shope, R. K., “Prima Facie Duty”, Journal of Philosophy, LXII (1965)Google Scholar. I cannot agree with the apparent endorsement of Ross's view by Ewing, A. C., “British Ethical Thought”, in Mace, C. A., British Philosophy in the Mid-Century (London, 1957), p. 73.Google Scholar
7 For general discussion see now Griffin, J., “Consequences”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, LXV (1964–1965).Google Scholar
8 A similar amendment has been suggested, independently, by McCloskey, H. J., “Ross and the Concept of a prima facie duty”, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 41 (1963).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
9 Ross, W. D., Foundations of Ethics (London, 1939), p. 86.Google Scholar
10 Prichard, H. A., “Does Moral Philosophy rest on a Mistake?” Mind, XXI (1912).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
11 Prichard, H. A., Moral Obligation (London, 1949), pp. 142–162.Google Scholar
12 Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica (Cambridge, 1903)Google Scholar; references to 1959 edition.
13 Moore, G. E., Ethics (London, 1912)Google Scholar; references to reset 1955 edition.
14 Moore, G. E., Principia Ethica, p. xxii, reference section 92.Google Scholar
15 Principia Ethica, p. xxiiGoogle Scholar, reference section 94; The Right and the Good, p. 30.Google Scholar
16 Principia Ethica, p. x.Google Scholar
17 Moore, G. E., “A Reply to my Critics”, in Schilpp, P. A., The Philosophy of G. E. Moore (New York, 2nd ed. 1952), p. 563.Google Scholar
- 2
- Cited by