Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-30T15:20:49.215Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Demarcating Contextualism and Contrastivism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  10 June 2021

Abstract

In this paper I argue that there is a significant but often overlooked metaphysical distinction to be made between contextualism and contrastivism. The orthodox view is that contrastivism is merely a form of contextualism. This is a mistake. The contextualist view is incompatible with certain naturalist claims about the metaphysical nature of concepts within whichever domain is being investigated, while the contrastivist view is compatible with these claims. So, choosing one view over the other will involve choosing to affirm or deny a significant metaphysical claim. As such, a demarcation ought to be put in place between contextualism and contrastivism.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy, 2021

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Blaauw, Martijn, ‘Contrastive Belief’ in Blaauw, Martijn, Contrastivism in Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2013).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stewart, ‘How to be a Fallibilist’, Philosophical Perspectives, 2 (1988), 91123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stewart, ‘Contextualist solutions to epistemological problems: Scepticism, Gettier, and the lottery’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76 (1998), 289306.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cohen, Stewart, ‘Contextualism, Skepticism, and the Structure of Reasons’, Philosophical Perspectives, 13 (1999), 5789.Google Scholar
DeRose, Keith, ‘Contextualism and Knowledge Attributions’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52 (1992), 913–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith, ‘Solving the Skeptical Problem’, The Philosophical Review, 104 (1995), 152.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
DeRose, Keith, (1999). ‘Contextualism: An Explanation and Defense’ in Greco, John & Sosa, Ernest, The Blackwell Guide to Epistemology (London: Blackwell, 1999).Google Scholar
Dretske, Fred, Knowledge and the Flow of Information (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1981).Google Scholar
Driver, Julia, ‘Luck and Fortune in Moral Evaluation’ in Blaauw, Martijn, Contrastivism in Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2013).Google Scholar
Garfinkel, Alan, Forms of Explanation: Rethinking the Questions in Social Theory (London: Yale University Press, 1981).Google Scholar
Heller, Mark, ‘The Proper Role for Contextualism in an Anti-Luck Epistemology’, Philosophical Perspectives, 13 (1999), 115–29.Google Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher, ‘Farewell to Binary Causation’, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 26 (1996a), 267–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hitchcock, Christopher, ‘The Role of Contrast in Causal and Explanatory Claims’, Synthese, 107 (1996b), 395419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kamp, Hans, ‘The Paradox of the Heap’, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 147 (1981), 225–77.Google Scholar
Kennedy, Christopher, ‘Vagueness and Grammer: The Semantics of Relative and Absolute Gradable Adjectives’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 30 (2007), 145.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kornblith, Hilary, Knowledge and its place in nature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kratzer, Angela, ‘What ‘Must’ and ‘Can’ Must and Can Mean’, Linguistics and Philosophy, 1 (1977), 337–55.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kumar, Victor, ‘‘Knowledge’ as a natural kind term’, Synthese, 191 (2014), 439–57.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, ‘New work for a theory of universals’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 61 (1983), 343–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, ‘Elusive Knowledge’, Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 74 (1996), 549–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lipton, Peter, ‘Contrastive Explanation’, Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplements, 27 (1990), 247–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacFarlane, John, ‘Relativism and Disagreement’, Philosophical Studies, 132 (2007), 1731.Google Scholar
MacFarlane, John, ‘Nonindexical Contextualism’, Synthese, 166 (2009), 231–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maslen, Cei, ‘Causes, contrasts, and the nontransitivity of causation’ in Hall, Ned, Paul, L. A., & Collins, John, Causation and Counterfactuals (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Menzies, Peter, ‘Difference-making in Context’ in Hall, Ned, Paul, L. A., & Collins, John, Causation and Counterfactuals (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2004a).Google Scholar
Menzies, Peter, ‘Causal Models, Token Causation, and Processes’, Philosophy of Science, 71 (2004b), 820–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Menzies, Peter, ‘Causation in Context’ in Price, Huw & Corry, Richard, Causation, Physics, and the Constitution of Reality: Russell's Republic Revisited (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2007).Google Scholar
Menzies, Peter, ‘Platitudes and Counterexamples’ in Beebee, Helen, Hitchcock, Christopher, & Menzies, Peter, The Oxford Handbook of Causation (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009).Google Scholar
Millikan, Ruth Garrett, White Queen Psychology and Other Essays for Alice (Cambridge MA: MIT Press, 1993).Google Scholar
Neta, Ram, ‘Contextualism and the Problem of the External World’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 66 (2003a), 131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neta, Ram, ‘Skepticism, Contextualism, and Semantic Self-Knowledge,’ Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 67 (2003b), 396411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northcott, Robert, ‘Causation and Contrast Classes’, Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy, 139 (2008), 111–23.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, ‘Why There Isn't a Ready-Made World’, Synthese, 51 (1982), 141–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan, ‘From Contextualism to Contrastivism’, Philosophical Studies: An International Journal for Philosophy in the Analytic Tradition, 119 (2004), 73103.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan, ‘Contrastive Causation’, The Philosophical Review, 114 (2005), 297328.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan, ‘The Contrast-sensitivity of Knowledge Ascriptions’, Social Epistemology, 22 (2008), 235–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan, ‘Causal Contextualism’ in Blaauw, Martijn, Contrastivism in Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2013).Google Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan, ‘Grounding in the image of causation’, Philosophical Studies, 173 (2016), 49100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schaffer, Jonathan & Knobe, Joshua, ‘Contrastive Knowledge Surveyed’, Noûs, 46 (2012), 675708.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, ‘Classy Pyrrhonism’ in Walter Sinnott-Armstrong, Pyrrhonian Skepticism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, Moral Skepticisms (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter, ‘A Contrastivist Manifesto’, Social Epistemology, 22 (2008), 257–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Snedegar, Justin, Contrastive Reasons (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2017).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stanley, Jason & Szabó, Zoltán Gendler, ‘On Quantifier Domain Restriction’, Mind and Language, 15 (2000), 219–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Peter, ‘Causation and Explanation’ in Strawson, Peter, Analysis and Metaphysics: An Introduction to Philosophy (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1992).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, Bas, The Scientific Image (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1980).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Westerståhl, Dag, ‘Aristotelian Syllogisms and the Generalized Quantifiers’, Studia Logica: An International Journal for Symbolic Logic, 48 (1989), 577–85.CrossRefGoogle Scholar