Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-m6dg7 Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T23:09:12.926Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Creating Facts and Values

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  30 January 2009

Ruth Anna Putnam
Affiliation:
Wellesley College

Extract

Moral sceptics maintain that there are no objective moral values, or that there is no moral knowledge, or no moral facts, or that what looks like a statement which makes a moral judgment is not really a statement and does not have a truth-value. All of this is rather, unclear because all of it is negative. It will be necessary to remove some of this unclarity because my aim in this paper is to establish a proposition which may be summarized by saying: even if there are no objective moral values in one sense, there are objective moralvalues in another sense, and the latter values are good enough to do some of the jobs that objective values in the first sense would have done. A useful analogy might be that of a person who has lost her hand and has been given a prosthesis. In one sense the prosthesis is not as real (because man-made) as the hand, in another sense it is just as real (both are physical objects); most importantly, the person can do with the prosthesis enough of what she could do with the hand to make do.

Type
Articles
Copyright
Copyright © The Royal Institute of Philosophy 1985

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

1 MacIntyre, Alasdair, After Virtue (London: Duckworth, 1981), 38.Google Scholar

2 Jean-Paul, Sartre, L'Existentialisme est un Humanisme. I quote from Bernard, Frechtman's translation in Jean-Paul, Sartre, Essays in Existentialism, Wade Baskin, (ed.) (New York: The Citadel Press, 1965), 55.Google Scholar

3 Goodman, Nelson, Ways of Worldmaking (hereafter WW) (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company, 1978).Google Scholar

4 WW, 91.

5 Arieti, Silvano, Creativity (New York: Basic Books, 1976), Ch. 11.Google Scholar

6 WW, 97.

7 WW, 102.

8 Harris, Roy, ‘The Basis of Artistic Creation in Music’, in Maxwell Anderson et al., The Bases of Artistic Creation (hereafter BAC) (New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1942), 27.Google Scholar

9 Rhys Carpenter, ‘The Basis of Artistic Creation in Painting’, in BAC, 58.

10 James, William, Pragmatism and the Meaning of Truth (Cambridge, Ma.: Harvard University Press, 1978), 98.Google Scholar

11 WW, 96, 97.

12 Erich Fromm, ‘The Creative Attitude’ in Creativity and its Cultivation Anderson, Harold H. (ed.) (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1959).Google Scholar

13 Fromm, 48.

14 Rorty, Richard, Consequences of Pragmatism (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1982), xiii.Google Scholar

15 This work was supported in part by a grant from the National Endowment for the Humanities.