Hostname: page-component-669899f699-vbsjw Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2025-05-04T10:25:31.203Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Emptiness of Naturalism

Joint Winner of the Philosophy Essay Prize Competition 2023

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  18 March 2025

Abstract

I argue that the term ‘naturalism’ is so empty of meaning that it is not suitable for serious theorizing in philosophy. In particular, I argue that the question of whether or not some theory or thesis should count as naturalistic is an empty verbal dispute with no further theoretical significance. I also discuss naturalism construed as a methodological thesis and argue that any plausible version will collapse into triviality. Lastly, I briefly discuss the idea that naturalism is not a thesis at all but rather a ‘stance’ and suggest that this too succumbs to the charge of emptiness. I conclude that we should stop talking about naturalism altogether.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Author(s), 2025. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Royal Institute of Philosophy

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Article purchase

Temporarily unavailable

References

Audi, Robert, Naturalism, Normativity & Explanation (Kraków: Copernicus Center Press, 2014).Google Scholar
Audi, Robert, ‘Scientific Naturalism and Normative Explanation’, in De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Liberal Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2022).Google Scholar
Bashour, Bana and Muller, Hans (eds.), Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications (New York: Routledge, 2014).Google Scholar
Benacerraf, Paul, ‘Mathematical Truth’, Journal of Philosophy, 70:19 (1973), 661–79.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Broad, Charlie D., Lectures on Psychical Research (New York: Humanities Press, 1962).Google Scholar
Cahill, Kevin and Raleigh, Thomas (eds.), Wittgenstein & Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2018).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chabada, Michal and Maco, Robert (eds.), Varieties of Naturalism in Contemporary Philosophy (Prague: Filosofia, Institute of Philosophy of the Czech Academy of Science, 2021).Google Scholar
Chalmers, David, The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Chalmers, David, ‘The Content and Epistemology of Phenomenal Belief”, in Smith, Q. and Jokic, A. (eds.), Consciousness: New Philosophical Perspectives (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003).Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam, Language and Mind (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1968).Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam, Powers and Prospects: Reflections on Human Nature and the Social Order (London: Pluto Press, 1996).Google Scholar
Chomsky, Noam, ‘The Mysteries of Nature: How Deeply Hidden?’, in Bricmont, J. and Franck, J. (eds.), Chomsky Notebook (NY: Columbia University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
Clark, Kelly J. (ed.), A Companion to Naturalism (Hoboken, NJ: Wiley-Blackwell, 2015).Google Scholar
Cohen, Jack, The Case for Religious Naturalism: A Philosophy for the Modern Jew (Eugene, OR: Wipf and Stock, 2019).Google Scholar
Collins, John, ‘Naturalism without Metaphysics’, in Fischer, E. and Collins, J. (eds.), Experimental Philosophy, Rationalism, and Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2015).Google Scholar
Crane, Tim and Mellor, Hugh, ‘There Is No Question of Physicalism’, Mind, 99 (1990), 185206.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crisp, Thomas, ‘Presentism, Eternalism and Relativity Physics’, in Craig, W. and Smith, Q. (eds.), Einstein, Relativity and Absolute Simultaneity (London: Routledge, 2008).Google Scholar
Cucu, Alin, ‘Turning the Tables: How Neuroscience supports Interactive Dualism’, Mind and Matter, 21:2 (2024), 219–39.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Caro, Mario De and Macarthur, David (eds.), Naturalism and Normativity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010).Google Scholar
De Caro, Mario and Macarthur, David, ‘Introduction’, in De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Liberal Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2022).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ellis, Fiona, God, Value and Nature (New York: Oxford University Press, 2014).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Emery, Nina, Naturalism Beyond the Limits of Science (New York: Oxford University Press, 2023).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Enoch, David, Taking Morality Seriously (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Everett, Hugh III, ‘The Theory of the Universal Wavefunction’, in DeWitt, B. and Graham, N. (eds.), The Many-Worlds Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1973).Google Scholar
Feynman, Richard, Six Easy Pieces (New York: Perseus Books, 1994).Google Scholar
Field, Hartry, Science Without Numbers: A Defence of Nominalism (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980).Google Scholar
Fishman, Yonatan and Boudry, Maarten, ‘Does Science Presuppose Naturalism?’, Science & Education, 22:5 (2013), 921–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fleischman, Martin and Pons, Stanley, ‘Electrochemically Induced Nuclear Fusion of Deuterium’, Journal of Electroanalytical Chemistry and Interfacial Electrochemistry, 261:2 (1989), 301308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry, ‘Against Darwinism’, Mind and Language, 23:1 (2008), 124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, Jerry & Piattelli-Palmarini, Massimo, What Darwnin Got Wrong (New York: Farrar, Strauss Giroux, 2010).Google Scholar
Goetz, Stewart and Taliafero, Charles, Naturalism (Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans Press, 2008).Google Scholar
Harman, Gilbert, The Nature of Morality (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977).Google Scholar
Hartmann, Martin and Särkelä, Arvi (eds.), Naturalism and Social Philosophy: Contemporary Perspectives (Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, 2023).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hempel, Carl, Philosophy of Natural Science (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1966).Google Scholar
Hempel, Carl, ‘Reduction: Ontological and Linguistic Facets’, in Suppes, P., Morgenbesser, S., and White, M. (eds.), Philosophy, Science, and Method: Essays in Honor of Ernest Nagel (New York: St Martin's Press, 1969).Google Scholar
Hendry, Robin, ‘Prospects for Strong Emergence in Chemistry’, in Paoletti, M. and Orilia, F. (eds.), Philosophical and Scientific Perspectives on Downward Causation (London: Routledge, 2017).Google Scholar
Hendry, Robin, ‘Emergence in Chemistry: Substance and Structure’, in Gibb, S., Hendry, R., and Lancaster, T. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Emergence (London: Routledge, 2019).Google Scholar
Horwich, Paul, ‘Naturalism and the “Linguistic Turn”’, in Bashour, B. and Muller, H. (eds.), Contemporary Philosophical Naturalism and Its Implications (London: Routledge, 2014).Google Scholar
Kemp, Gary, ‘Is everything a Set? Quine and (Hyper)Pythagoreanism’, The Monist, 100:2 (2017), 155–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kopersky, Jeffrey, ‘Theism, Naturalism, and Scientific Realism’, Epistemology and Philosophy of Science, 53:3 (2017), 152–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ladyman, James and Ross, Don, Every Thing Must Go: Metaphysics Naturalized (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David, On the Plurality of Worlds (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).Google Scholar
McLaughlin, Brian, ‘The Rise and Fall of British Emergentism’, in Beckermann, A., Flohr, H., and Kim, J. (eds.), Emergence or Reduction? Essays on the Prospects of Nonreductive Physicalism (Berlin: De Gruyter, 1992).Google Scholar
Montero, Barbara and Papineau, David, ‘A Defense of the Via Negativa Argument for Physicalism’, Analysis, 65:3 (2005), 233–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Monton, Bradley, Seeking God in Science: An Atheist Defends Intelligent Design (Toronto, ON: Broadview Press, 2009).Google Scholar
Morganti, Matteo, ‘Liberal Naturalism, Ontological Commitment and Explanation’, in De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Liberal Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2022).Google Scholar
Ney, Alyssa, ‘Physicalism as an Attitude’, Philosophical Studies, 138 (2008), 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oppy, Graham, Naturalism and Religion: A Contemporary Philosophical Investigation (Routledge, 2018).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David, Philosophical Naturalism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Papineau, David, ‘The Rise of Physicalism’, in Gillett, C. and Loewer, B. (eds.), Physicalism and Its Discontents (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Papineau, David, ‘Naturalism’, in Zalta, E. and Nodelman, U. (eds.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism/ (2007).Google Scholar
Peacocke, Arthur, ‘Welcoming the “Disguised Friend” – Darwinism and Divinity’, in Pennock, R. (ed.), Intelligent Design Creationism and Its Critics: Philosophical, Theological, and Scientific Perspectives (Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2001).Google Scholar
Peels, Rik, ‘Ten Reasons to Embrace Scientism’, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 63 (2017), 1121.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Plantinga, Alvin, Where the Conflict Really Lies: Science, Religion, and Naturalism (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Poland, Jeffrey, Physicalism: The Philosophical Foundations (Oxford: Clarendon, 1994).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Price, Henry H., Philosophical Interactions with Parapsychology (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 1995).Google Scholar
Putnam, Hilary, Philosophy of Logic (London: Allen & Unwin, 1971).Google Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O., ‘Carnap and Logical Truth’, Synthese, 12:4 (1954), 350–74.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O., ‘Ontological Reduction and the World of Numbers’, Journal of Philosophy, 61:7 (1964), 209–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O., Ontological Relativity and Other Essays (New York: Columbia University Press, 1969).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, Willard V. O., ‘Whither Physical Objects?’, Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 39 (1976), 303–10.Google Scholar
Raleigh, Thomas, ‘Philosophy of Perception and Liberal Naturalism’, in De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Liberal Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2022).Google Scholar
Rea, Michael, World Without Design (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 2004).Google Scholar
Ritchie, Jack, Understanding Naturalism (Durham: Acumen Press, 2008).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ritchie, Jack, ‘Naturalism as a Stance’, in De Caro, M. and Macarthur, D. (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Liberal Naturalism (London: Routledge, 2022).Google Scholar
Rockwell, Teed, ‘Naturalistic Theism’, Essays in the Philosophy of Humanism, 25:2 (2017), 209–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spiegel, Thomas J., Naturalism, Quietism, and the Threat to Philosophy (Basel: Schwabe Verlagsgruppe, 2021).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Spiegel, Thomas J., ‘Why Naturalism Cannot (Merely) Be an Attitude’, Topoi, 42:3 (2023), 745–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Strawson, Peter F., Individuals: An Essay in Descriptive Metaphysics (London: Routledge, 1959).Google Scholar
Stroud, Barry, ‘The Charm of Naturalism’, Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 70:2 (1996), 4355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van Fraassen, Bas, The Empirical Stance (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2002).Google Scholar
Wilson, Alastair, The Nature of Contingency: Quantum Physics as Modal Realism (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2020).CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Jessica, ‘On Characterizing the Physical’, Philosophical Studies, 131 (2006), 6199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar