Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-dh8gc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-05T05:48:49.687Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

What Preferences Really Are

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

Daniel M. Hausman holds that preferences in economics are total subjective comparative evaluations—subjective judgments to the effect that something is better than something else all things told—and that economists are right to employ this conception of preference. Here, I argue against both parts of Hausman’s thesis. The failure of Hausman’s account, I continue, reflects a deeper problem, that is, that preferences in economics do not need an explicit definition of the kind that he seeks. Nonetheless, Hausman’s labors were not in vain: his accomplishment is that he has articulated a useful model of the theory.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Previous versions were read at the 2016 Philosophy of Science Association meetings in Atlanta, the 2017 European Philosophy of Science Association meetings in Exeter, and seminars at Stockholm University, Aarhus University, and KTH Royal Institute of Technology in Stockholm. I am grateful to the participants—especially Lawrence Boland, Philip Kitcher, and Victor Moberger—for thoughtful feedback; to Marc Berman and Katherine Kinzler for taking the time to discuss the cognitive science; and to Francesco Guala, Daniel Hausman, Mats Ingelström, Aki Lehtinen, Ivan Moscati, Michiru Nagatsu, Robert Östling, Daniel Ramöller, Raffaele Rodogno, and three anonymous referees for helpful comments on earlier drafts. Errors, as always, remain my own. This project is sponsored in part by two John Templeton Foundation grants, titled “Virtue, Happiness, and the Meaning of Life” and “Happiness and Well-Being: Integrating Research across the Disciplines.”

References

Andreas, Holger. 2017. “Theoretical Terms in Science.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2017/entries/theoretical-terms-science.Google Scholar
Angner, Erik. 2013. “Is Empirical Research Relevant to Philosophical Conclusions?Res Philosophica 90 (3): 343–63..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angner, Erik 2016. A Course in Behavioral Economics. 2nd ed. London: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Angner, Erik, and Loewenstein, George. 2012. “Behavioral Economics.” In Handbook of the Philosophy of Science: Philosophy of Economics, ed. Maki, Uskali, 641–90. Amsterdam: Elsevier.Google Scholar
Binmore, Ken. 2009. Rational Decisions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Boulier, Bryan L., and Goldfarb, Robert S. 1991. “Pisces Economicus: The Fish as Economic Man.” Economics and Philosophy 7 (1): 8386..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carnap, Rudolf. 1966/1966. An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science. ed. Gardner, Martin. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Fiske, Susan T., and Taylor, Shelley E. 2017. Social Cognition: From Brains to Culture. 3rd ed. London: SAGE.Google Scholar
Franks, Nigel R., Dechaume-Moncharmont, François-Xavier, Hanmore, Emma, and Reynolds, Jocelyn K. 2009. “Speed versus Accuracy in Decision-Making Ants: Expediting Politics and Policy Implementation.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 364 (1518): 845–52..Google ScholarPubMed
Frigg, Roman, and Hartmann, Stephan. 2017. “Models in Science.” In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. Zalta, Edward N. Stanford, CA: Stanford University. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2017/entries/models-science/.Google Scholar
Guala, Francesco. 2017. “Preferences: Neither Behavioural nor Mental.” DEMM Working Paper no. 2017-05, Department of Economics, Management and Quantitative Methods at Università degli Studi di Milano. https://ideas.repec.org/p/mil/wpdepa/2017-05.html.Google Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. 2012. Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Hausman, Daniel M. 2013. “A Reply to Lehtinen, Teschl and Pattanaik.” Journal of Economic Methodology 20 (2): 219–23..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kagel, John H., Battalio, Raymond C., and Green, Leonard. 1995. Economic Choice Theory: An Experimental Analysis of Animal Behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Keeney, Ralph L., and Raiffa, Howard. 1993. Decisions with Multiple Objectives: Preferences and Value Tradeoffs. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kuhn, Thomas S. 2012. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 4th ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lancaster, Kelvin J. 1966. “A New Approach to Consumer Theory.” Journal of Political Economy 74 (2): 132–57..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehtinen, Aki. 2013. “Preferences as Total Subjective Comparative Evaluations.” Journal of Economic Methodology 20 (2): 206–10..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
List, Christian, Elsholtz, Christian, and Seeley, Thomas D. 2009. “Independence and Interdependence in Collective Decision Making: An Agent-Based Model of Nest-Site Choice by Honeybee Swarms.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B 364 (1518): 755–62..Google ScholarPubMed
Loewenstein, George, and Angner, Erik. 2003. “Predicting and Indulging Changing Preferences.” In Time and Decision: Economic and Psychological Perspectives on Intertemporal Choice, ed. Loewenstein, George, Read, Daniel, and Baumeister, Roy F., 351–91. New York: Russell Sage.Google Scholar
Luce, R. Duncan, and Raiffa, Howard. 1957. Games and Decisions: Introduction and Critical Survey. New York: Wiley.Google Scholar
Mandler, Michael. 1999. Dilemmas in Economic Theory: Persisting Foundational Problems of Microeconomics. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mas-Colell, Andreu, Whinston, Michael D., and Green, Jerry R. 1995. Microeconomic Theory. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Moscati, Ivan. 2012. Review of Preference, Value, Choice, and Welfare, by Daniel M. Hausman. Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 5 (2): 125–31..Google Scholar
Moscati, Ivan 2018. Measuring Utility: From the Marginal Revolution to Neuroeconomics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagatsu, Michiru, and Põder, Kaire. 2017. “Economists’ Concept of Choice: An Experimental Study.” Unpublished manuscript, University of Helsinki.Google Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1961. The Structure of Science: Problems in the Logic of Scientific Explanation. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Neumann, John von, and Morgenstern, Oskar. 1944. Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Robbins, Lionel. 1932. An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Weisberg, Michael. 2007. “Three Kinds of Idealization.” Journal of Philosophy 104 (12): 639–59..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wicksteed, Philip H. 1933. The Common Sense of Political Economy and Selected Papers and Reviews on Economic Theory, Vol. 1, ed. Lionel Robbins. Rev. ed. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Zajonc, Robert B. 1968. “Attitudinal Effects of Mere Exposure.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 9 (2), pt. 2:127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zajonc, Robert B. 1980. “Feeling and Thinking: Preferences Need No Inferences.” American Psychologist 35 (2): 151–75..CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Zajonc, Robert B., and Markus, Hazel. 1982. “Affective and Cognitive Factors in Preferences.” Journal of Consumer Research 9 (2): 123–31..CrossRefGoogle Scholar