Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-gbm5v Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-26T16:24:58.405Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Underdetermination and the Problem of Identical Rivals

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

If two theory formulations are merely different expressions of the same theory, then any problem of choosing between them cannot be due to the underdetermination of theories by data. So one might suspect that we need to be able to tell distinct theories from mere alternate formulations before we can say anything substantive about underdetermination, that we need to solve the problem of identical rivals before addressing the problem of underdetermination. Here I consider two possible solutions: Quine proposes that we call two theories identical if they are equivalent under a reconstrual of predicates, but this would mishandle important cases. Another proposal is to defer to the particular judgements of actual scientists. Consideration of an historical episode—the alleged equivalence of wave and matrix mechanics—shows that this second proposal also fails. Nevertheless, I suggest, the original suspicion is wrong; there are ways to enquire into underdetermination without having solved the problem of identical rivals.

Type
Confirmation and Statistical Inference
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

In writing and revising this paper, I benefitted from helpful conversations with Craig Callender, Jonathan Cohen, and a number of fellow graduate students. Part of the work was done with the support of a National Science Foundation graduate fellowship. A version of this paper was presented to the Southern California Philosophy Conference in October 2001.

References

Cartwright, Nancy (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Churchland, Paul (1998), “Conceptual Similarity Across Sensory and Neural Diversity”, in On the Contrary. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 81112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, Ronald N. (1994), “The Cognitive Structure of Scientific Theories”, The Cognitive Structure of Scientific Theories 61:276296.Google Scholar
Glymour, Clark (1980), Theory and Evidence. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, Adolf (1960), “The Duhemian Argument”, The Duhemian Argument 27:7587.Google Scholar
Hanson, Norwood Russell (1963), The Concept of the Positron. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Horwich, Paul (1982), “How to Choose between Empirically Indistinguishable Theories”, How to Choose between Empirically Indistinguishable Theories 79:6177.Google Scholar
Hughes, R. I. G. (1989), The Structure and Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2001a), “Real Realism: The Galilean Strategy”, Real Realism: The Galilean Strategy 110:151197.Google Scholar
Kitcher, Philip (2001b), Science, Truth, and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, Larry, and Leplin, Jarrett (1993), “Determination Undeterred: Reply to Kukla”, Determination Undeterred: Reply to Kukla 53:816.Google Scholar
Mühlhölzer, Felix (1994), “Scientific Explanation and Equivalent Descriptions”, in W. Salmon and G. Walters (eds.), Logic, Language, and the Strucuture of Scientific Theories. Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial, University of Konstanz, 21–24 May 1991, 119138. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Muller, F. A. (1997), “The Equivalence Myth of Quantum Mechanics”, The Equivalence Myth of Quantum Mechanics 28:3561, 219–247.Google Scholar
Poincaré, Henri ([1908] 1952), Science and Method. Translated by Maitland, Francis. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Quine, Quine Willard Van (1975), “Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World”, Empirically Equivalent Systems of the World 9:313328.Google Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans (1951), The Rise of Scientific Philosophy. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans (1958), The Philosophy of Space & Time. Translated by Reichenbach, Maria and Freund, John. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
Sklar, Lawrence (1985), “Saving the Noumena”, in Philosophy & Spacetime Physics, 4972. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Suppes, Patrick (1968), “The Desirability of Formalization in Science”, The Desirability of Formalization in Science 65:651664.Google Scholar
Thornton, Stephen T., and Rex, Andrew (1993), Modern Physics for Scientists and Engineers. Fort Worth, TX: Saunders College Publishing.Google Scholar
Wilson, Mark (1980), “The Observational Uniqueness of Some Theories”, The Observational Uniqueness of Some Theories 77:208233.Google Scholar