Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-r5fsc Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T22:58:19.005Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Two Outbreaks of Lawlessness in Recent Philosophy of Biology

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Elliott Sober*
Affiliation:
University of Wisconsin-Madison
*
Department of Philosophy, 5185 Helen C. White Hall, University of Wisconsin, Madison, WI 53706, USA.

Abstract

John Beatty (1995) and Alexander Rosenberg (1994) have argued against the claim that there are laws in biology. Beatty's main reason is that evolution is a process full of contingency, but he also takes the existence of relative significance controversies in biology and the popularity of pluralistic approaches to a variety of evolutionary questions to be evidence for biology's lawlessness. Rosenberg's main argument appeals to the idea that biological properties supervene on large numbers of physical properties, but he also develops case studies of biological controversies to defend his thesis that biology is best understood as an instrumental discipline. The present paper assesses their arguments.

Type
Symposium: Are There Laws of Biology?
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

My thanks to Robin Andreasen, André Ariew, John Beatty, Robert Brandon, Wyman Brantley, Martin Carrier, Terry Horgan, Harold Kincaid, Alexander Rosenberg, Chris Stephens, and Ann Wolfe for useful discussion.

References

Anscombe, G. (1975), “Causality and Determination”, in Sosa, E. (ed.), Causation and Conditionals. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 6381.Google Scholar
Beatty, J. (1995), “The Evolutionary Contingency Thesis”, in Wolters, G. and Lennox, J. (eds.), Concepts, Theories, and Rationality in the Biological Sciences: The Second Pittsburgh-Konstanz Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 4581.Google Scholar
Carrier, M. (1995), “Evolutionary Change and Lawlikeness”, in Wolters, G. and Lennox, J. (eds.), Concepts, Theories, and Rationality in the Biological Sciences: The Second Pittsburgh-Konstanz Colloquium in the Philosophy of Science. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, pp. 8397.Google Scholar
Dretske, F. (1977), “Laws of Nature”, Philosophy of Science 44: 248268.10.1086/288741CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fisher, R. (1930), The Genetical Theory of Natural Selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.10.5962/bhl.title.27468CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fodor, J. (1975), The Language of Thought. New York: Thomas Crowell.Google Scholar
Forster, M. and Sober, E. (1994), “How to Tell When Simpler, More Unified, or Less Ad Hoc Theories will Provide More Accurate Predictions”, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45: 135.10.1093/bjps/45.1.1CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kimura, M. (1983), The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.10.1017/CBO9780511623486CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mills, S. and Beatty, J. (1979), “The Propensity Interpretation of Fitness”, Philosophy of Science 46: 263286.10.1086/288865CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nelson, G. and Platnick, N. (1981), Systematics and Biogeography. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
Rosenberg, A. (1994), Instrumental Biology or the Disunity of Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1984), The Nature of Selection. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1988), Reconstructing the Past. Cambridge, MA.: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1993), Philosophy of Biology. Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
Sober, E. (1994), “Temporally Oriented Laws”, in From a Biological Point of View. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 233252.10.1017/CBO9780511624940.013CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. (1996), “Evolution and Optimality—Feathers, Bowling Balls, and the Thesis of Adaptationism.” 1995–96 Philosophic Exchange 26: 4157.Google Scholar
Sober, E. and Lewontin, R. (1982), “Artifact, Cause, and Genic Selection”, Philosophy of Science 47: 157180.10.1086/289047CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sober, E. and Wilson, D. (1994), “A Critical Review of Philosophical Work on the Units of Selection Problem”, Philosophy of Science 61: 534555.10.1086/289821CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Williams, M. (1970), “Deducing the Consequences of Evolution”, Journal of Theoretical Biology 29: 343385.10.1016/0022-5193(70)90103-7CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed