Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-8ctnn Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T07:15:39.890Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Theory-Conjunction and Mercenary Reliance

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

J. D. Trout*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Loyola University of Chicago, 6525 North Sheridan Road, Chicago, IL 60626, USA.

Abstract

Scientific realists contend that theory-conjunction presents a problem for empiricist conceptions of scientific knowledge and practice. Van Fraassen (1980) has offered a competing account of theory-conjunction which I argue fails to capture the mercenary character of epistemic dependence in science. Representative cases of theory-conjunction developed in the present paper show that mercenary reliance implies a “principle of epistemic symmetry” which only a realist can consistently accommodate. Finally, because the practice in question involves the conjunction of theories, a version of realism more robust than the “entity realism” of Cartwright (1983, 1989) and Hacking (1983) is required to explain the success of theory-conjunction.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1992

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Much of this paper was written while I was a Mellon Postdoctoral Fellow at Bryn Mawr College, and I am grateful for my time there. I am likewise grateful to Dick Boyd, Phil Gasper, Justin Schwartz, Rob Wilson, and an anonymous referee of this journal for their comments on this work.

References

Boyd, R. (1973), “Realism, Underdetermination, and a Causal Theory of Evidence”, Nous 7: 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. (1983), “On the Current Status of the Issue of Scientific Realism”, Erkenntnis 19: 4590.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Boyd, R. (1985), “The Logician's Dilemma: Deductive Logic, Inductive Inference and Logical Empiricism”, Erkenntnis 22: 197252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1983), How the Laws of Physics Lie. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Cartwright, N. (1989), Nature's Capacities and Their Measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Cox, A. and Hart, R. (1986), Plate Tectonics: How It Works. Palo Alto, CA: Blackwell Scientific Publications.Google Scholar
Demopoulos, W. (1982), Review of The Scientific Image by Bas C. van Fraassen, Philosophical Review 91: 603607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Fine, A. (1986), “Unnatural Attitudes: Realist and Instrumentalist Attachments to Science”, Mind 95: 149179.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, M. (1983), Foundations of Space-Time Theories: Relativistic Physics and Philosophy of Science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science: A Cognitive Approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Hacking, I. (1983), Representing and Intervening. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardwig, J. (1985), “Epistemic Dependence”, Journal of Philosophy 82: 335349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1990), “The Division of Cognitive Labor”, Journal of Philosophy 87: 522.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lehrer, K. (1977), “Social Information”, Monist 60: 473487.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Piper, J. (1987), Paleomagnetism and the Continental Crust. New York: Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), “Explanation and Reference”, in Philosophical Papers. Vol. 2, Mind, Language and Reality. New York: Cambridge University Press, pp. 196214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1978), Meaning and the Moral Sciences. Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
Repp, B. and Frost, R. (1988), “Detectability of Words and Nonwords in Two Kinds of Noise”, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 84: 19291932.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Samuel, A. (1987), “Lexical Uniqueness Effects on Phonemic Restoration”, Journal of Memory and Language 26: 3656.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schroeder, M. (1968), “Reference Signal for Signal Quality Studies”, Journal of the Acoustical Society of America 44: 17351736.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schwartz, M. and Shaw, L. (1975), Signal Processing: Discrete Spectral Analysis, Detection, and Estimation. New York: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
Steams, S. (1975), Digital Signal Analysis. Rochelle Park, NJ: Hayden Book Company.Google Scholar
Tarling, D. (1971), Principles and Applications of Paleomagnetism. London: Chapman & Hall.Google Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1980), The Scientific Image. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar