Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T15:46:36.373Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Reinterpretation of Harré's Copernican Revolution

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  14 March 2022

Edward Mackinnon*
Affiliation:
California State University, Hayward

Extract

Rom Harré's proposed Copernican Revolution in the philosophy of science is a very ambitious undertaking. It challenges established views, proposes a radically new model for scientific explanation, and forces a rethinking of the foundations of the field. In his treatment of the natural sciences, Harré rejects all deductivist accounts of scientific explanation (whether these accounts are fashioned by rationalists or empiricists) basically on the grounds that such accounts seriously distort the methods of explanation actually operative in science. In the social sciences Harré, in collaboration with Secord, rejects mechanistic, positivistic, and behavioristic accounts of human behavior [5]. In place of these discarded interpretations he substitutes a new realism which stresses the role that models play in supplying accounts of observed patterns of phenomena in terms of the things and processes whose interactions are responsible for the manifest phenomena. This revolution, if successfully carried out, would indeed be a valuable contribution to the philosophy of science.

Type
Discussion
Copyright
Copyright © 1975 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

REFERENCES

Harré, R. Theories and Things. London: Sheed and Ward, 1961.Google Scholar
Harré, R. An Introduction to the Logic of the Sciences. London: Macmillan, 1963.Google Scholar
Harré, R. The Philosophies of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1972.Google Scholar
Harré, R. The Principles of Scientific Thinking. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1970.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Harré, R. and Secord, P. The Explanation of Social Behavior. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1972.Google Scholar
Körner, S. Experience and Theory: An Essay in the Philosophy of Science. New York: Humanities Press, 1966.Google Scholar
Körner, S. Categorial Frameworks. New York: Barnes and Noble, 1970.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, E. Truth and Expression: The 1968 Hecker Lectures. New York: Newman Press, 1971.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, E. The Problem of Scientific Realism. New York: Prentice-Hall, 1974.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, E.Theoretical Entities and Metatheories.” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science 3 (1972): 105117.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
MacKinnon, E.Ontic Commitments of Quantum Mechanics.” In Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 13. Edited by Cohen, R. S. and Wartofsky, M. W. Dordrecht, Holland: D. Reidel, 1974.Google Scholar
MacKinnon, E.The Role of Models in the Development of Matrix Mechanics.” (forthcoming)Google Scholar
Miller, D.Back to Aristotle.” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23 (1972): 6978.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sellars, W.Some Reflections on Language Games.” In Science, Perception and Reality. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963.Google Scholar
Sellars, W. Science and Metaphysics: Variations on Kantian Themes. New York: Humanities Press, 1968.Google Scholar
Strawson, P. Individuals. New York: Doubleday, 1963.Google Scholar
Strawson, P.Analysis, Science, and Metaphysics.” In The Linguistic Turn. Edited by Rorty, R. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1967.Google Scholar