Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-02T22:07:39.518Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Reference Invariance and Truthlikeness

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Ilkka Niiniluoto*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Helsinki
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, P.O. Box 24 (Unioninkatu 40), University of Helsinki, Helsinki 00014, Finland.

Abstract

A holistic account of the meaning of theoretical terms leads scientific realism into serious troubles. Alternative methods of reference fixing are needed by a realist who wishes to show how reference invariance is possible in spite of meaning variance. This paper argues that the similarity theory of truthlikeness and approximate truth, developed by logicians since the mid 1970s, helps to make precise the idea of charitable theoretical reference. Comparisons to the recent proposals by Kitcher and Psillos are given. This argument helps to undermine the scepticist meta-induction about theories, and thereby to reevaluate Laudan's alleged confutation of scientific realism.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1997

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Boyd, R. (1973), “Realism, Underdetermination, and the Causal Theory of Evidence”, Noûs 7: 112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Brown, H.I. (1977), Perception, Theory, and Commitment: The New Philosophy of Science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cummiskey, D. (1992), “Reference Failure and Scientific Realism: a Response to the Meta-induction”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43: 2140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Devitt, M. and Sterelny, K. (1987), Language and Reality: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Language. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Field, H. (1973), “Theory Change and the Indeterminacy of Reference”, The Journal of Philosophy 70: 462481.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1988), Explaining Science. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hardin, C.L. and Rosenberg, A. (1982), “In Defense of Convergent Realism”, Philosophy of Science 49: 604615.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kitcher, P. (1993), The Advancement of Science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Kordig, C.R. (1971), The Justification of Scientific Change. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kripke, S. (1971), Naming and Necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
Kroon, F. (1988), “Realism and Descriptivism”, in Nola, R. (ed.), Relativism and Realism in Science. Dordrecht: Kluwer, pp. 141167.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Leplin, J. (1979), “Reference and Scientific Realism”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 10: 265285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984a), Science and Values. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
Laudan, L. (1984b), “Realism without the Real”, Philosophy of Science 51: 156162.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Martens, D.B. (1993), “Close Enough to Reference”, Synthese 95: 357377.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McAllister, J.W. (1993), “Scientific Realism and the Criteria of Theory-Choice”, Erkenntnis 38: 203222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1984), Is Science Progressive? Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1987), Truthlikeness. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Niiniluoto, I. (1990), “Measuring the Success of Science”, in Fine, A., Forbes, M., and Wessels, L. (eds.), PSA 1990 vol. 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 435445.Google Scholar
Nola, R. (1980), “Fixing the Reference of Theoretical Terms”, Philosophy of Science 47: 505531.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Oddie, G. (1986), Likeness to Truth. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, S. (1994a), “A Philosophical Study of the Transition from the Caloric Theory of Heat to Thermodynamics: Resisting the Pessimistic Meta-induction”, Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 25: 153190.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Psillos, S. (1994b), Science and Realism: A Naturalistic Investigation into Scientific Enquiry. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of London.Google Scholar
Psillos, S. (1996), “Scientific Realism and the ‘Pessimistic Induction’”, Philosophy of Science 63 (Proceedings): S306S314.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1975), Mind, Language, and Reality (Philosophical Papers vol. 2). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Putnam, H. (1978), Meaning and the Moral Sciences. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Scheffler, I. (1967), Science and Subjectivity. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
Smith, P. (1981), Realism and the Progress of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Weston, T. (1992), “Approximate Truth and Scientific Realism”, Philosophy of Science 59: 5374.CrossRefGoogle Scholar