Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-rdxmf Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T15:36:07.394Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

The Reception of Relativity in American Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  05 June 2023

Sander Verhaegh*
Affiliation:
Tilburg Center for Moral Philosophy, Epistemology, and Philosophy of Science (TiLPS), Tilburg University, Tilburg, the Netherlands
Rights & Permissions [Opens in a new window]

Abstract

Historians have shown that philosophical discussions about the implications of relativity significantly shaped the development of European philosophy of science in the 1920s. Yet little is known about American debates from this period. This article maps the first responses to Einstein’s theory in three U.S. philosophy journals and situates these papers within the local intellectual landscape. I argue that these discussions (1) stimulated the development of a distinctly American branch of philosophy of science and (2) paved the way for the logical empiricists who emigrated to the United States in the years before World War II.

Type
Article
Creative Commons
Creative Common License - CCCreative Common License - BY
This is an Open Access article, distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution licence (http://creativecommons.org/licenses/by/4.0/), which permits unrestricted re-use, distribution and reproduction, provided the original article is properly cited.
Copyright
© The Author(s), 2023. Published by Cambridge University Press on behalf of the Philosophy of Science Association

1. Introduction

The early development of philosophy of science is deeply intertwined with the reception of special and general relativity. Einstein’s work challenged prevalent perspectives about space and time and stimulated philosophers to rethink the relation between science and philosophy. Logical empiricism partly emerged out of neo-Kantian debates about relativity, British philosophers frequently discussed relativity after the 1919 Royal Society announcement about the results of Eddington’s eclipse expedition, and the Bergson-Einstein debate sparked an intense discussion among French intellectuals (e.g., Reichenbach Reference Reichenbach1920; Schlick Reference Schlick1922; Carr Reference Carr1920; Haldane Reference Haldane1921; Bergson Reference Bergson1922; Meyerson Reference Meyerson1925). Much as the crises in the foundations of mathematics had stimulated the development of scientific philosophy at the turn of the century, the theory of relativity pushed philosophers in new directions in the wake of World War I.

In recent years, scholars have enriched our understanding of the history of philosophy of science by studying it through the lens of this reception history. They have reconstructed the complex interplay between neo-Kantian, conventionalist, and positivist responses to relativity in the works of, among others, Carnap, Cassirer, Reichenbach, Schlick, and Weyl (Friedman Reference Friedman1999; Ryckman Reference Ryckman2005). They have documented its reception within the British philosophical community (Desmet Reference Desmet2007; Sanchez-Ron Reference Sanchez-Ron, Lehner, Renn and Schemmel2012). And they have analyzed the debate on Einstein’s work in France (Biezunski Reference Biezunski and Thomas1987; Demoures Reference Demoures2007). Finally, there has been a lot of interest in the evolution of Einstein’s own philosophical perspective (Howard Reference Howard1984; Ryckman Reference Ryckman2017).

Curiously, however, little is known about the philosophical reception of relativity in the United States. Historians have analyzed the first responses from American physicists, mathematicians, and astronomers (Goldberg Reference Goldberg1984; Crelinsten Reference Crelinsten2006), but it is unclear how Einstein’s theory influenced local philosophers. This is surprising because (1) a quick search reveals that U.S. philosophy journals published dozens of papers and reviews on relativity, and (2) some of the most prominent European voices in the debate—Carnap, Carr, Cassirer, Einstein, Reichenbach, Weyl, and Whitehead—eventually emigrated to the United States. If there was a community of scientific philosophers, however small, in North America in the 1920s, then studying its response to relativity might shed new light on the integration of logical empiricism and the subsequent institutionalization of philosophy of science.Footnote 1

This article reconstructs the reception of relativity in American philosophy. I chart the more than 70 philosophical articles and reviews on the subject in three U.S. philosophy journals and situate these responses within the U.S. intellectual landscape, showing that its implications were studied by scholars representing a variety of philosophical traditions, including pragmatism, idealism, and (neo-)realism. I argue that the debate stimulated the development of American scientific philosophy and, thereby, the integration of logical empiricism in the 1930s. Before I turn to the philosophical responses, however, I outline the reception of relativity within U.S. physics because it will prove instructive to compare the two reception histories.

2. The scientific reception of relativity

Early-20th-century American physics has long had a reputation for its empiricist orientation. Unlike many of their European colleagues, U.S. physicists typically presupposed a strictly empiricist philosophy of science, demanding a tighter connection between theory and observation than was usual at the time. Daniel Kevles writes about the community’s “arid form of empiricism” (Reference Kevles1979, 37), and Stanley Goldberg argues that physicists almost exclusively relied on empirical arguments in deciding between theories. The idea that theory choice depends on experimental evidence and theoretical virtues (e.g., simplicity or generality), widely accepted in Europe, was considered heresy in the United States (Goldberg Reference Goldberg1988, 79). U.S. physicists, Goldberg concludes, were often skeptical about abstract theorizing and exhibited a “general eschewal of metaphysics, which was identified with European culture” (Reference Goldberg1984, 267).

This empiricist approach is particularly evident in the community’s first responses to special and general relativity. In recent decades, historians have reconstructed the theory’s reception in a large number of countries, including Germany, England, France, China, Russia, Japan, Italy, Spain, and Belgium.Footnote 2 This growing body of work reveals “the salience of national inflections” and shows that the reception of relativity was often colored by local scientific cultures (Glick Reference Glick1987, vii). In the decade after Einstein published his 1905 papers on the subject, special relativity was heavily debated in Germany but ignored in France, and the British were aware of it but largely stuck to the ether theory. In the United States, the responses were mixed, but both proponents and critics generally appealed to empiricist arguments in their writings. Whereas aesthetic-mathematical considerations played a major role in the responses of European scientists—even in England—American physicists generally ignored the question of whether the theory is mathematically elegant or contributes to a more unified physical theory.Footnote 3

The first American response to special relativity—Lewis and Tolman’s “The Principle of Relativity, and Non-Newtonian Mechanics”—was published in 1909. The two Massachusetts Institute of Technology (MIT) scientists discussed a number of recent experiments and analyzed to what degree the results supported special relativity. Likely inspired by A. A. Michelson’s 1908 Nobel Prize—the first to be awarded to a U.S. scientist—Lewis and Tolman focused mostly on the implications of the former’s ether experiments. Although the, at the time, diverse responses to these experiments show that their results can be variously interpreted, Lewis and Tolman claimed that the body of evidence left only one satisfactory explanation, namely, Lorentz’s conclusion that all moving bodies contract in the line of their motion (Reference Lewis and Tolman1909, 711–12). Einstein, the two acknowledged, was going a bit “beyond existing facts” in rejecting absolute motion altogether. But they were reasonably confident about the possibility of “further verification” because Einstein had deduced additional empirical consequences from his hypothesis (Lewis and Tolman Reference Lewis and Tolman1909, 712, 718). As such, Lewis and Tolman concluded, the principle of relativity appeared to be “established on a pretty firm basis of experimental fact” (712–13). The first English-language book on relativity, by the U.S. mathematician R. D. Carmichael, also relied on empiricist arguments. Although many mathematicians evaluated the theory’s formal properties, Carmichael exclusively focused on its empirical support. Like Lewis and Tolman, his conclusions were cautiously optimistic. Carmichael concluded that “there is no experimental evidence which is undoubtedly opposed” to the theory, although there may be indirect evidence in its favor (Reference Carmichael1912, 18–19, 63–65).Footnote 4

Opponents of relativity theory appealed to empiricist considerations, too. W. F. Magie, one of the founding members of the American Physical Society, objected to what he deemed to be a metaphysical theory, arguing that “Michelson-Morley” only supported the conclusion that there is no way to determine the relative motion of Earth and the ether when the observer and the source of light are moving along with our planet (Reference Magie1912, 288). To abandon absolute motion altogether would be to draw an empirically unwarranted conclusion. His colleague L. T. More, a professor of physics at the University of Cincinnati, was equally worried that Einstein’s principle obliterated “the boundary between science and metaphysics” and argued that it transcended the discussion of postulates “determined by experience” (Reference More1911, 196). Interestingly, the two critics disagreed about where to draw the distinction between physics and metaphysics. Magie was a staunch defender of the ether theory and believed it to be the only empirically plausible explanation of the transmission of light. More objected to any speculation about the nature of the cosmos and submitted that both “atoms and ethers … are metaphysical creations” (Reference More1910, 815). A true scientist, More argued, is exclusively concerned with the formulation of laws “deduced mathematically from experimental data” (Reference More1909, 876).

Empiricism is not just a view about epistemic justification. Typically, empiricists also believe that theoretical terms should have the appropriate semantic connection to observational concepts. Indeed, some of the most sophisticated treatises of the period also emphasized this conceptual side of empiricism. In doing so, they often followed Peirce, who had argued that the meaning of a hypothesis is determined by its experimental effects, or J. B. Stallo, a German-born philosopher of science who had published The Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics in Reference Stallo1882. Stallo defended a quasi-positivist perspective and warned against the reification of basic physical concepts. He primarily used his approach to criticize what he deemed to be the metaphysical assumptions of Newtonian physics, rejecting absolute space, absolute time, and absolute motion. In eliminating from science “its latent metaphysical elements,” he hoped to contribute to the scientific endeavor to gain “a sure foothold on solid empirical ground, where the real data of experience may be reduced without ontological prepossessions” (Reference Stallo1882, 8).Footnote 5

Both the theory of special relativity and that of general relativity stimulated American physicists to further reflect on the conceptual foundations of their discipline, not in the least because Einstein himself appeared to give a positivist spin to his discovery. In writing about the “profound influence” of Mach and in arguing that a “concept does not exist for the physicist until he has the possibility of discovering whether or not it is fulfilled in an actual case” (Reference Einstein1917, 22), Einstein seemed to presuppose a positivist perspective, inspiring U.S. scientists to adopt a similar approach.Footnote 6 In 1927, the Harvard physicist P. W. Bridgman published The Logic of Modern Physics, a book that applied the lessons of, among others, Stallo and Mach to the recent revolutions in physics (Reference Bridgman1927, v–vi). His solution was to adopt a strictly empiricist, or operationist, attitude toward the concepts of physics, exemplified in his mantra that we “mean by any concept nothing more than a set of operations” (Reference Bridgman1927, ix–x). Although Bridgman was critical of general relativity, he believed he was criticizing Einstein on Einsteinian grounds, using the latter’s perspective on “what the concepts useful in physics are and should be” (Reference Bridgman1927, 4). In equating the meaning of statements about simultaneity with the concrete operations we use to determine whether two events occur simultaneously, Einstein had developed an operational analysis of time in his 1905 papers. Moreover, he had repeated the point in his more popular Relativity: The Special and General Theory (Einstein Reference Einstein1917).

The crucial difference between Bridgman’s perspective and traditional approaches is the way concepts are conceived. Classical physicists often defined concepts in terms of properties. Newton, for example, defined absolute time as that what “of itself, and from its own nature flows equably without regard to anything external” (Bridgman Reference Bridgman1927, 4). The danger of this approach is that we might discover that there is nothing in nature that has these properties, so we are constantly confronted with scientific revolutions like the one sparked by Einstein. Bridgman instead proposed to define concepts in terms of operations. Applied to Newton’s concept of absolute time, this means that we do not understand its meaning “unless we can tell how to determine the absolute time of any concrete event”; once we see that the operations by which we measure time are relative, as Einstein demonstrated, we have to conclude that the concept is operationally “meaningless” (Bridgman Reference Bridgman1927, 5). In order to prevent similar revolutions in the future, we have to subject all concepts of physics to an operational analysis.

3. American philosophy at the turn of the century

Early discussions of relativity were mostly confined to a small circle of physicists, astronomers, and mathematicians. This changed in November 1919, when the Royal Society announced that Einstein’s predictions about the bending of starlight had been confirmed by Eddington’s solar eclipse expedition. In the years after the announcement, American media published hundreds of articles trying to explain the theory. Einstein was described as the “destroyer of space and time” and became a national celebrity when he visited the country in 1921 (Missner Reference Missner1985, 271–73). Given this widespread attention for topics that had traditionally been the domain of philosophy—space and time—it should not be a surprise that philosophers quickly started to write about relativity, too.

Historians often divide early-20th-century American philosophy into three distinct but partially overlapping schools: idealism, realism, and pragmatism (Kuklick Reference Kuklick2001; Campbell Reference Campbell2006, ch. 3). The most sizable of the three, the idealist movement, was skeptical about the empiricist approach that dominated the sciences. Most idealists believed that experimental findings can, at best, deliver a partial understanding of reality. Two hundred years of modern epistemology had shown that empiricism leads to skepticism because there is no way to determine whether our ideas correspond to an independently existing material world. Instead of blindly relying on science, we should accept that reality is mind dependent and that there are moral and spiritual dimensions to experience, too. The idealists held that it is the philosophers’ job to ground physical, moral, and religious truths and unify these domains into a coherent system. Only philosophy, idealists believed, can “investigate the grounds … of the whole body of truth with a view to its unity and meaning as a whole” (Ormond Reference Ormond1906, 3).

It is no coincidence that idealism dominated philosophy at the turn of the century because the development of philosophy as a distinct academic discipline was partly a response to the increasing influence of science in American academia. The establishment of dozens of new laboratories and polytechnics, the rise of experimental psychology, and the popularity of philosophically minded naturalists such as Ernst Haeckel and Herbert Spencer contributed to the feeling that philosophy was in danger of being swallowed by the sciences (Campbell Reference Campbell2006; Wilson Reference Wilson1990). In response to this threat, idealists helped found the first professional journals (e.g., Philosophical Review in 1892) and organizations (e.g., American Philosophical Association [APA] in 1902) to establish philosophy as an independent discipline. The first president of the APA, the idealist J. E. Creighton, argued that philosophy had to protect itself against scientists who “wholly unschooled in the subject … feel themselves competent … to write philosophical books” (Reference Creighton1902, 232).

The idealist movement began to be challenged in the first decade of the 20th century. In England, the revolt was led by G. E. Moore and Bertrand Russell, two Cambridge graduates who objected to the views of their idealist colleagues and sought to replace them with a variant of realism. Something similar happened in the United States. Two recent graduates from “the other Cambridge”—W. P. Montague and R. B. Perry—objected to the views of Josiah Royce, America’s best-known idealist (Montague Reference Montague1902; Perry Reference Perry1902). Inspired by Russell’s work, they argued for a more scientific approach to philosophy. Whereas their idealist predecessors distinguished between scientific findings and philosophical synthesis, these “new realists” viewed themselves as part of an “era of united and complimentary endeavor” (Holt et al. Reference Holt, Marvin, William Pepperell Montague, Pitkin and Gleason Spaulding1912, 21). They promoted the use of mathematical logic, analytic methods, and a piecemeal approach, dealing with “one problem at a time” instead of attempting to “answer all questions together” (Holt et al., 21–26). The “most notable feature of a realistic philosophy,” the realists believed, “is the emancipation of metaphysics from epistemology” (Holt et al., 32). Whereas the idealists had put epistemology center stage, using the theory of knowledge to draw conclusions about the nature of reality, the realists turned this relation on its head, arguing that the knowledge relation is just one of many relations between independently existing objects.

The second, and nowadays best-known, alternative to idealism was developed by the pragmatists. Building on the work of, among others, Peirce, James, and Dewey, pragmatism became an influential yet diverse philosophical movement that was more closely tied to the empiricist tradition in the sciences. William James had been a crucial figure in the development of experimental psychology, and Peirce’s aforementioned criterion of meaning implied that two hypotheses have the same content if they have the same observational consequences. James first invoked C. S. Peirce’s pragmatic test in an 1898 paper and used it to argue that many speculative debates about the nature of reality are pointless. Dewey had started out as a Hegelian but came to replace his idealist approach with a naturalized perspective on man, mind, and morality.

4. The philosophical reception of relativity

The 1919 Royal Society announcement gave new impetus to the debate between idealists, realists, and pragmatists. In the decade after the news about Eddington’s expedition, American philosophy journals published dozens of papers and reviews on relativity, discussing its foundations and philosophical implications.Footnote 7 Table 1 lists most of the papers published in three prominent American philosophy journals—the Journal of Philosophy, Philosophical Review, and The Monist—between 1921 and 1930 and shows that these periodicals published a host of articles on relativity theory.Footnote 8 Table 2 lists most of the reviews of books on relativity theory in two of these journalsFootnote 9 and reveals that the philosophical community also kept a close eye on foreign publications on the subject, even if they were written by physicists.

Table 1. Selection of Papers on Relativity Theory Published in Three Prominent American Philosophy Journals between 1921 and 1930

Author Year Title Journal
E. E. Slosson 1921 Eddington on Einstein Jphil
V. A. Endersby 1921 Einsteinian Space and the Probable Nature of Being Monist
J. E. Turner 1921 Some Philosophic Aspects of Scientific Relativity Jphil
J. E. Fries 1921 “Relativity”: A Searchlight on Human Perception Monist
A. L. Hammond 1921 Appearance and Reality in the Theory of Relativity PhilReview
W. B. Smith 1921 Relativity and Its Philosophic Implications Monist
H. A. Wadman 1922 Relativity, Old and New Jphil
T. de Laguna 1922 The Nature of Space—I Jphil
T. de Laguna 1922 The Nature of Space—II Jphil
T. de Laguna 1922 Point, Line, and Surface, as Sets of Solids Jphil
A. A. Merrill 1923 Duration and Relativity Jphil
W. P. Montague 1924 The Einstein Theory and a Possible Alternative PhilReview
Filmer Northrop 1925 Relativity and the Relation of Science to Philosophy Monist
L. E. Akeley 1925 The Problem of the Specious Present and Physical Time Jphil
J. R. Haldane 1925 Gravitation: A Simplified Theory of Relativity Monist
W. Gordin 1926 The Philosophy of Relativity Jphil
O. L. Reiser 1926 The Problem of Time in Science and Philosophy PhilReview
E. Wind 1927 Alfred C. Elsbach’s Kant und Einstein Jphil
E. T. Mitchell 1927 Kantian Relativity Monist
A. E. Murphy 1927 Alexander’s Metaphysic of Space-Time (I) Monist
B. I. Gilman 1927 Relativity and the Lay Mind. I Jphil
B. I. Gilman 1927 Relativity and the Lay Mind. II Jphil
W. A. Shimer 1927 Evolution of Relativity Monist
Filmer Northrop 1928 The Theory of Relativity and the First Principles of Science Jphil
Filmer Northrop 1928 A Physical Interpretation of the Theory of Relativity Jphil
J. E. Turner 1929 The Essential Distinction between Science and Philosophy PhilReview
R. P. Richardson 1929 Relativity and Its Precursors Monist
A. E. Murphy 1929 The Anti-Copernican Revolution Jphil
F. P. Hoskyn 1929 The Problem of Motion Jphil
H. Margenau 1929 The Problem of Physical Explanation Monist
J. A. Lynch 1929 Time-Systems as Perspectives Jphil
J. E. Turner 1930 Relativity Without Paradox Monist
J. MacKaye 1930 The Theory of Relativity: For What Is It a Disguise? Jphil
Filmer Northrop 1930 Concerning the Phil. Consequences of the Theory of Relativity Jphil
A. A. Merrill 1930 Limitations Jphil
Filmer Northrop 1930 The Unitary Field Theory of Einstein and Its Bearing on … Monist
F. P. Hoskyn 1930 The Relativity of Inertial Mass Jphil
A. O. Lovejoy 1930 The Dialectical Argument Against Absolute Simultaneity. I Jphil
A. O. Lovejoy 1930 The Dialectical Argument against Absolute Simultaneity. II Jphil

Jphil, Journal of Philosophy; PhilReview, Philosophical Review.

Table 2. Selection of Reviews of Books on Relativity Theory in the Journal of Philosophy and Philosophical Review between 1921 and 1930

Reviewer Year Reviewed Book Journal
J. E. Trevor 1921 Relativity. The Special and General Theory by A. Einstein PhilReview
H. R. Smart 1921 General Principle of Relativity by H. W. Carr PhilReview
E. B. McGilvary 1921 The Concept of Nature by A. N. Whitehead PhilReview
J. E. Turner 1922 The Reign of Relativity by R. B. Haldane JPhil
E. Kasner 1922 General Principle of Relativity by H. W. Carr JPhil
E. Kasner 1922 Space and Time in Contemporary Physics by M. Schlick JPhil
E. Kasner 1922 On Gravitation and Relativity by R. A. Sampson JPhil
H. R. Smart 1922 The Rudiments of Relativity by J. P. Dalton PhilReview
J. E. Creighton 1922 The Reign of Relativity by R. B. Haldane PhilReview
T. de Laguna 1922 The Absolute Relations of Time and Space by A. A. Robb JPhil
T. de Laguna 1922 Philosophy and the New Physics by L. Rougier JPhil
H. R. Smart 1922 Space, Time and Gravitation by A. S. Eddington PhilReview
C. I. Lewis 1923 La Notion d’Espace by D. Nys JPhil
J. A. Leighton 1923 A Theory of Monads by H. W. Carr PhilReview
H. T. Costello 1924 Relativity, Logic, and Mysticism. Arist. Soc. Suppl. Vol. III. JPhil
H. R. Smart 1924 Einstein’s Theory of Relativity by E. Cassirer PhilReview
G. Cunningham 1925 Relativity, Logic, and Mysticism. Arist. Soc. Suppl. Vol. III. PhilReview
E. H. Kennard 1925 Sidelights on Relativity by A. Einstein PhilReview
C. I. Lewis 1925 Scientific Thought by C. D. Broad PhilReview
H. R. Smart 1925 La Déduction Relativiste by E. Meyerson PhilReview
W. P. Montague 1925 A Theory of Monads by H. W. Carr JPhil
H. T. Costello 1925 La Déduction Relativiste by E. Meyerson JPhil
C. W. Cobb 1926 The Origin, Nature, and Infl. of Relativity by G. D. Birkhoff JPhil
H. R. Smart 1927 Relativity and the Critical Philosophy by F. Kassel PhilReview
A. C. Benjamin 1927 The Logic of Modern Physics by P. W. Bridgman JPhil
E. Nagel 1927 An Experiment with Time by J. W. Dunne JPhil
W. van de Walle 1928 The Logic of Modern Physics by P. W. Bridgman PhilReview
E. H. Kennard 1928 The Analysis of Matter by B. Russell PhilReview
R. M. Blake 1928 Temps, Espace, Relativité by A. Metz JPhil
R. M. Blake 1928 The Theory of Relativity by L. Siff JPhil
A. C. Benjamin 1928 The Evolution of Scientific Thought by A. D’Abro JPhil
V. F. Lenzen 1929 The Analysis of Matter by B. Russell JPhil
E. B. McGilvary 1930 The Nature of the Physical World by A. S. Eddington JPhil
E. B. McGilvary 1930 Science and the Unseen World by A. S. Eddington JPhil
A. E. Murphy 1930 The Nature of the Physical World by A. S. Eddington PhilReview
P. P. Wiener 1930 Essai Philos. sur la Théorie de la Relativité by M. C. Dupont JPhil
S. K. Langer 1930 Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre by H. Reichenbach JPhil

Jphil, Journal of Philosophy; PhilReview, Philosophical Review.

A closer study of the papers listed in Table 1 shows that the theory was discussed by philosophers from a variety of schools. Idealists, realists, and pragmatists, but also philosophers representing smaller movements such as Bergsonism and phenomenology, responded to relativity, and many of them were convinced that Einstein’s principle supported the perspective they had been developing themselves. H. R. Smart, who regularly reviewed books on relativity (Table 2), said that many philosophers viewed relativity as a “welcome vindication of their particular philosophical doctrines” (Reference Smart1925, 511), and Russell wrote that “there has been a tendency, not uncommon in the case of a new scientific theory, for every philosopher to interpret the work of Einstein in accordance with his own metaphysical system” (Reference Russell1926, 331).

Many idealists felt vindicated by relativity because they took Einstein to have shown that there is no mind-independent order of temporal relations. Realists had argued that space and time have an objective existence, but Einstein’s theory, these idealists held, revealed this to be a mistake. Whereas the aforementioned Montague had characterized reality as a distribution of qualities over an independently existing four-dimensional manifold of spatial and temporal positions (Reference Montague, Edwin, Marvin, Montague, Perry, Pitkin and Spaulding1912, sec. 12), these idealists believed Einstein to have shown that even a basic property like length belongs not to an independently existing object but exists “as a relation of observer-and-observed” (Smith Reference Smith1921, 505). In drawing these conclusions, they followed the British philosopher R. B. Haldane, who argued that “if the principle of relativity is well-founded the very basis of the New Realism seems to disappear into vapour” (Haldane Reference Haldane1921, 273). And they were likely inspired by the London-based philosopher H. W. Carr, who held that Einstein’s theory shows that there is no “concrete four-dimensional space-time” that serves as the substratum of our activities but that there are only the “perception-actions of infinite individual creative centres in mutual relation” (Carr Reference Carr1920, 162). In 1922, Carr even organized a debate at the Aristotelian Society on the thesis that the “principle of relativity … is in complete accord with the neo-idealist doctrine in philosophy, and in complete disaccord with the fundamental standpoint of every form of neo-realism” (Carr et al. Reference Carr, Percy Nunn, Whitehead and Wrinch1922, 123).Footnote 10

In the United States, this reading was defended by a number of philosophers, including mathematician-philosopher William B. Smith. In a paper titled “Relativity and Its Philosophic Implications,” Smith developed the thesis that relativity was a further step into the direction of a view in which “objects … are not discoveries but the creations of psychic activity” (Reference Smith1921, 505). The Tulane professor was working on a book titled Mind: The Maker and was convinced that Einstein’s theory fitted “completely and perfectly … with the general world-view that I have long cherished and am gradually shaping into expression” (Reference Smith1921, 509). Another example is the Russian-American philosopher Wolf Gordin, who argued that Einstein had “disproved” those who would “banish philosophy from the realm of reality”; Gordin believed that Einstein had set in motion an “an unsurmized renaissance of philosophy, mathematics, logic, epistemology, and metaphysics” that combined non-Euclidean geometry with Cantor’s work on infinity and “Hegel’s dialectics” (Reference Gordin1926, 518).

Many realists, on the other hand, were critical of relativity, and some of them even tried to dismiss the theory.Footnote 11 Montague, for example, published an analysis of special relativity and concluded that Einstein’s ideas are internally inconsistent. One of his central arguments was a version of the twin paradox, in which one of two twin brothers travels back and forth into space and discovers, upon return, that he has aged less than his stay-at-home brother. Applying the relativity of motion, such that the stay-at-home brother could also be viewed as the one who has been traveling back and forth in the opposite direction, Montague derived the paradoxical conclusion that each twin is younger than his brother (Reference Montague1924, 156). In order to resolve the paradox, Montague proposed an alternative to special relativity built on the assumption that the speed of light is, pace Einstein, affected by the velocity of its source. In fact, Montague even sketched an experiment designed to test his alternative and called upon the readers of Philosophical Review to help and fund it: “The cost of the experiment might run to $20,000. … Perhaps some of you will be willing to pray that there be sent to me a kind-hearted rich man who will take a sporting chance and put up the necessary funds” (Reference Montague1924, 162).

Montague was not the only philosopher to make use of the twin paradox to dismiss special relativity. A few years later, Arthur Lovejoy published an article sketching a similar paradox (Reference Lovejoy1931). Lovejoy, who had a stake in the debate because he had long defended a position that has been dubbed “temporal realism” (Kurz Reference Kurz1966, 354), believed it was simply inconsistent to dismiss the assumption “that there is a single universal order of temporal relations … in which every event can be unequivocally assigned” (Lovejoy Reference Lovejoy1930, 617). Lovejoy’s most important objection to relativity, however, concerned Einstein’s theory of meaning. Turning Bridgman’s modus ponens into a modus tollens, Lovejoy accepted the latter’s diagnosis that Einstein presupposed a “radically experimental theory of meaning” but used it to reject special relativity. It is simply “preposterous,” Lovejoy argued, to suppose that “no term can ever signify anything more than what is actually given in the verifying experience”:

astronomers were long able to judge of the probable distances of remote stars … only by observing and measuring the “apparent brightness” of the stars. The degree of brightness, that is, was the sole experimental criterion (admittedly a poor one) of distance which they could apply; they did not even then, however, suppose themselves to mean by the star’s distance its “apparent brightness.” (Reference Lovejoy1930, 620)

Mocking Einstein’s criterion, Lovejoy argued that it implied that if a bedridden patient observes two men, one outside in the rain and another entering her room with wet clothing, her inference that rain had fallen upon both could not have the same meaning in the two cases because it had been verified in a different way (Reference Lovejoy1930, 628). Instead, Lovejoy proposed an alternative theory of meaning in which an experimental finding is “the sign or circumstantial evidence of something else,” not the “meaning” of the term (Reference Lovejoy1930, 620).

Not everyone accepted Lovejoy’s argument. A substantial group of philosophers embraced Bridgman’s conclusions and interpreted them as confirming a broadly pragmatist orientation. They felt emboldened by the Logic of Modern Physics because they read it as offering an essentially Peircean perspective on scientific concepts. J. S. Bixler argued that Bridgman’s “new physics” confirmed the “pragmatic theory that knowledge is directed toward the consequences of experimental operations” (Reference Bixler1930, 214). And Ernest Nagel saw Bridgman’s perspective as a new version of the approach Peirce had developed 50 years before:

Many years ago Peirce made clear that our ideas are to mean all the experimentally verifiable consequences which follow our acting upon them. Since Peirce was bred in the laboratory … it is not surprising that critically conscious scientists should have, independently, voiced a full-throated endorsement of many of his positions. … With Bridgman we may say that “the concept is synonymous with the corresponding set of operations.”Footnote 12 (Reference Nagel1929, 172)

W. E. Van de Walle even suggested that Bridgman’s book could have been titled “The Evidence from Physics for Pragmatism” (Reference Van de Walle1928, 286). Einstein had ignited an intellectual firestorm, and one of the country’s most prominent physicists advanced a perspective that sounded very much like the view pragmatists had been defending for decades.

5. Scientific philosophy

Many of the aforementioned papers are relatively shallow when compared to some of the work that was published in, for instance, Germany and England. It is unlikely that philosophers such as Smith, Gordin, Montague, Lovejoy, Bixler, and van de Walle fully understood Einstein’s theory. Montague’s version of the twin paradox had already been resolved when he published his paper.Footnote 13 And Lovejoy’s reading of Einstein’s theory of meaning was quickly rejected by Evander McGilvary, who showed that the Swiss-German professor had never claimed that concepts ought to be defined in terms of the operations we use to test them. Einstein, McGilvary argued, defended a subtler criterion in which concepts are only indirectly tied to operations. A circle, for example, is not defined in terms of the method we use to determine whether a particular shape qualifies as a circle. Conversely, we use the definition of a circle—a figure consisting of points equidistant from a given point in a two-dimensional plane—to find a method for “how to go about finding out whether a figure is a circle” (McGilvary Reference McGilvary1931, 427).

Still, several American philosophers made lasting contributions in the wake of Einstein’s discoveries. One important example is Theodore de Laguna, whose work on geometry helped found the field of mereotopology (Reference De Laguna1922a, Reference De Laguna1922b, Reference De Laguna1922c). De Laguna, a Bryn Mawr professor, proposed to define standard spatial concepts such as “point” and “coordinate position” in terms of region-based concepts such as “solid” and “connection,” instead of the other way around, and is today still considered “a forerunner” in the area of qualitative topological reasoning (Varzi Reference Varzi, Aiello, Pratt-Hartmann and van Benthem2007, 979). Not only did it influence Whitehead’s work on the relation of extensive connection (Whitehead Reference Whitehead1929, 287), but present-day mathematicians still view him as one of the first scholars to develop a region-based geometry (Pratt-Hartmann Reference Pratt-Hartman, Aiello, Pratt-Hartmann and van Benthem2007, 91). Another set of valuable contributions came from Yale, where an interdisciplinary group of philosophers and physicists—Filmer Northrop, Henry Margenau, and Fred Hoskyn—regularly contributed to debates about the methodological implications of relativity (see Table 1). All three were critics of Bridgman’s view and aimed to develop a theory of meaning that allows theoretical constructs.Footnote 14 Whereas Bridgman held that we employ different concepts of length if we use different operations to measure length in different domains, Margenau believed that such a criterion dissolves reality into an “unmanageable variety of discrete concepts without logical coherence”:

If carried to its consequence … [t]here would be no way of telling … why a time interval read from a clock is more closely related conceptually to a time interval measured by astronomical observations than to weight determined by means of a balance. (Margenau Reference Margenau1931, 16–17)

Instead, Margenau and Northrop introduced a separate category of concepts—“concepts by postulation”—and argued that modern physical theories, including Einstein’s mechanics, require such notions. Although concepts by postulation cannot be operationally defined, theories involving such concepts are testable because one can derive consequences from them that can be directly verified (Northrop Reference Northrop1939, 434–35).Footnote 15

Although only a few of the articles listed in Table 1 have withstood the test of time, it would be a mistake to conclude that this literature has been rightly ignored by historians. On the contrary, these philosophical discussions about relativity are significant because they contributed to the development of a uniquely American branch of philosophy of science. Whereas the first decades of the century were marked by philosophical disputes between idealists, realists, and pragmatists, participants in the debate about relativity contributed to the development of a more scientifically oriented philosophy. Even some idealists, who had traditionally been suspicious of overly scientistic approaches (see sec. 3), now explicitly recognized the “the dependence of philosophy upon the findings” of the special sciences (Northrop Reference Northrop1925, 6). Unlike the situation in Italy, where “neo-idealists just dismissed the question of the philosophical consequences of relativity” because the “idea of an idealist science” would be “a contradiction in terms” (Reeves Reference Reeves and Thomas1987, 206–8; Sanchez-Ron Reference Sanchez-Ron, Lehner, Renn and Schemmel2012), several American idealists helped promote the idea that philosophy should become more scientific. And although some opponents of idealism were skeptical about the value of metaphysical speculation, most of them could live with a speculative movement that had “its feet on the ground, however much its head may swim” (Costello Reference Costello1931, 245). Einstein’s theory, in other words, stimulated philosophers to develop more scientifically informed perspectives. Perry, the aforementioned realist, even wrote a paper in which he signaled that the scholastic disputes that had characterized U.S. philosophy before World War I (see sec. 3) had made a place for an “era of philosophical peace” because science had given everyone “something new to think about” (Perry Reference Perry1928, 311–12).Footnote 16

Conversely, physicists and mathematicians also became increasingly interested in the philosophical foundations of their disciplines. Bridgman and Margenau were certainly not the only scientists to do work in the philosophy of physics. The aforementioned Carmichael wrote a paper on the “philosophical implications” of relativity (Carmichael Reference Carmichael and Bryan1927) and published a textbook titled The Logic of Discovery (Carmichael Reference Carmichael1930). The mathematician G. D. Birkhoff developed an axiomatization of general relativity (much like Reichenbach had done in Berlin), adding a chapter on the theory’s “philosophical influence” (Birkhoff Reference Birkhoff1925). And the Columbia mathematician C. J. Keyser, one of the American postulate theorists, published a book titled Mathematical Philosophy in which he aimed to bring philosophers and mathematicians closer to one another (Keyser Reference Keyser1922).

Together, this growing community of scientists and philosophers started to develop a new field that was variously called “scientific philosophy” or “philosophy of science.”Footnote 17 In 1925, C. I. Lewis signaled the rise of a “new movement in philosophy” inspired by the “revolutionary advances in logic, in mathematical, and in physical theory” and noted that “the partitions between these subjects have become thin or disappeared” as they all developed “in the direction of greater comprehensiveness and increased rigor” (Reference Lewis1925, 410). Similar observations were made by Paul Schilpp, who recognized “a tendency in recent American philosophy which … may perhaps most adequately called and described as the philosophy of science” (Reference Schilpp1930, 276); by Frank Thilly, who noted the rise of “new movements” that “derive their inspiration from the methods and results of natural science … and seek … to avoid the metaphysical presuppositions of the older schools” (Reference Thilly1926, 522); and by Charles Morris, who recognized “many streams of activity” that contribute to “a wide convergence toward a unified philosophical science and scientific philosophy” (Reference Morris1935, 147–48; Verhaegh Reference VerhaeghForthcoming).

6. Logical empiricism

Although it is difficult to estimate the relative size of the community of philosophers and scientists involved in debates about the foundations of science, there is quite a lot of evidence that the American reception of logical empiricism was directly connected to the previously discussed debates. German and U.S. philosophers had worked in relative isolation since the First World War, but the philosophy of relativity functioned as a shared reference point when the Allied boycott on German scholarship was lifted in 1926. Whereas Reichenbach’s first two books on relativity, published during the years of the boycott, had been generally ignored, for example, his 1928 Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre was positively reviewed and regularly cited in the American literature (Langer Reference Langer1930; Northrop Reference Northrop1931). Susanne Langer, for example, praised Reichenbach’s approach to philosophy of science because it concerned “the philosophical reflection of a scientist, not the scientific speculation of a philosopher” like “Einstein, Whitehead, or Weyl” before him (Reference Langer1930, 611). Moritz Schlick, who had written one of the best-known philosophical works on relativity in the German-speaking world, was quickly invited to come and lecture in the United States. H. W. Stuart, chairman of Stanford’s philosophy department, had been reading Schlick’s exposition of Einstein’s theory and wrote that it would be his great pleasure to welcome him to California.Footnote 18 And Philipp Frank, Einstein’s successor in Prague, was invited to do a lecture tour in the United States, where he was greatly admired for his understanding of “modern physics and philosophy” and his competence “to treat these two fields jointly.”Footnote 19 Although the American reception of logical empiricism is commonly tied to its “philosophical” program, many of the first encounters between U.S. philosophers and logical empiricists were concerned with the philosophical implications of relativity.

The logical empiricists, in turn, were also interested in the perspectives on relativity that had been developed in the United States. Schlick read up on Bridgman’s work before he traveled to the United States and published a review of The Logic of Modern Physics in Die Naturwissenschaften. And Schlick’s student Herbert Feigl even acquired a Rockefeller fellowship to study with Bridgman at Harvard in the 1930–31 academic year. Carnap had already discovered the diverse Anglophone literature on relativity in 1923, when he had attended a congress of the American Mathematical Society in New York. In a letter to Reichenbach, Carnap described the growing “interest in … mathematical logic” and surveyed the Anglophone literature on relativity. His letter includes a list of English-language publications on Einstein’s theory (including, among others, Carmichael’s and Keyser’s books) and expresses his surprise about the amount of “valuable work that has been done and is important for us.”Footnote 20

The philosophy of relativity, in sum, stimulated European and American philosophers to get acquainted with each other’s work, thereby paving the way for the relatively warm reception of logical empiricism in the United States.Footnote 21 Some American philosophers even traveled to Europe to visit the Berlin Group and/or the Vienna Circle. The Yale philosopher Northrop acquired a fellowship to visit Reichenbach and Einstein in Berlin, describing Reichenbach’s work as exactly “the kind of thing we need in philosophy.”Footnote 22 The New York philosopher Sidney Hook visited Reichenbach in Germany and described Philosophy der Raum-Zeit-Lehre as “the most lucid and comprehensive exposition of the philosophical implications of the theory of relativity” (Hook Reference Hook1930, 159). And the critical realist C. A. Strong invited Feigl to come to his Italian residence in Fiesole in order to help the American philosopher acquire “a better understanding of Einstein’s theory of relativity.” Strong “was working on a metaphysical theory of space and time and wanted to find out to what extent his views were compatible with those of Einstein” (Feigl Reference Feigl, Fleming and Bailyn1969, 68). Feigl, in turn, traveled to the United States to work with Bridgman and learn more about his operationist approach to the philosophy of physics and, in doing so, helped spread the views of the Vienna Circle to some of the philosophers (most notably, C. I. Lewis and W. V. Quine) who would come to play an important role in the further promotion of logical empiricism in the United States.Footnote 23

A few years later, several members of this diverse community of European and American philosophers (idealists, pragmatists, operationists, realists, and logical empiricists) would become involved in the two boards of Philosophy of Science, which published its first issue in 1934, thereby contributing to the institutionalization of philosophy of science in North America. Indeed, the editorial and advisory boards of this new journal perfectly reflect the intellectually diverse community of philosophers of science working on relativity in this period. The team included—in addition to editor William Malisoff—Bridgman, Carnap, Feigl, Lovejoy, Margenau, Montague, Northrop, Reichenbach, Schlick, and Whitehead.

7. Conclusion

Historians have shown that philosophical debates about special and general relativity have shaped the development of philosophy of science. This article argued that the United States was no exception. The American intellectual climate had been characterized by (1) a deeply empiricist approach to science among physicists and (2) abstract discussions between idealists, realists, and pragmatists in philosophy. Throughout the 1920s, however, some members of all these groups came to focus on the philosophical implications of relativity, thereby giving rise to a substantial literature on Einstein’s theory in American philosophy journals. And although not all participants agreed on whether to accept general (or even special) relativity, the discussion helped stimulate an interdisciplinary movement that was variously called “scientific philosophy” or “philosophy of science.” Philosophers reflected on the consequences of modern physics, and physicists became interested in the philosophical foundations of their discipline. This article has provided an overview of these responses and argued that the discussions paved the way for the successful integration of logical empiricism in the 1930s. Americans were not just eager to learn about the views of their colleagues because Viennese philosophers had developed an analytic approach to philosophy or radically empiricist views about meaning and metaphysics. They were first and foremost interested in their views about Einstein’s theory because they themselves had debated the implications of relativity for more than a decade.

Acknowledgments

This research was funded by the European Research Council (ERC StG 2021, 101039904) and the Dutch Research Council (NWO VI.Vidi.201.115). I would like to thank David Atkinson, two anonymous referees, and the Exiled Empiricists project team for their valuable feedback and suggestions.

Footnotes

1 Existing work on the development of U.S. philosophy of science tends to focus on the “golden age” of American pragmatism (approx. 1898–1914) or on the period after the logical empiricists moved to the United States (1931 and later). An exception is Katzav and Vaesen (2022), although they are primarily interested in the development of speculative philosophy of science.

2 See, for example, Hu (2007), ten Hagen (2020), and the papers collected in Glick (Reference Glick1987).

3 Some U.S. physicists even explicitly argued against aesthetic arguments. See Magie (Reference Magie1912).

4 Carmichael mainly focused on Bucherer’s 1908 beta-ray experiments in his overview. He took these findings to offer indirect evidence because Bucherer presupposed the law of conservation of electric charge. Compare Lewis and Tolman (Reference Lewis and Tolman1909, 712).

5 Scholars disagree about whether Stallo, like, for example, Mach, anticipated some of Einstein’s arguments. See Bridgman (Reference Bridgman, Stallo and Bridgman1960, xxvi), Kevles (1979, 30), and Herbert (2001, ch. 2).

6 I write that he “seemed” to defend a positivist perspective because present-day scholars dismiss this interpretation (e.g., Howard 1984; Ryckman 2017).

7 Only few philosophical articles on relativity appeared before the 1919 announcement. See, for example, Carus (Reference Carus1913). Henderson (1993, 146–48) discusses Carus’s response.

8 This list is more or less complete depending on one’s selection criteria. I only included articles that discuss relativity, ignoring work on space and time in philosophy proper. Note that most but not all authors of the articles listed are American or based at a U.S. university.

9 That is, the Journal of Philosophy and Philosophical Review. The Monist rarely published reviews.

10 See Sanchez-Ron (2012) for a reconstruction of the British reception of relativity.

11 Already in 1913, Morris Cohen had warned realists “who assume an absolute time or space” that their theory might be “inconsistent” with the newest physical insights and “should at least reckon with the recent relativity theory of Einstein and Minkowsky” (Reference Cohen1913, 210–11).

12 See Verhaegh (2020). Verhaegh argues that Dewey and Lewis embraced operationism, too.

13 Einstein (1918) solved the paradox within the framework of general relativity. It is unclear whether Montague was aware of Einstein’s response.

14 In addition to his work on scientific concepts, Northrop was known for positing the existence of a macroscopic atom, which he thought was needed to explain atomic motion within the framework of general relativity (Northrop 1928). This theory generated quite some attention as an alternative to Whitehead’s cosmology, which itself was viewed as an alternative to general relativity (see Whitehead Reference Whitehead1929, 333). Northrop’s student Hoskyn compared Einstein’s and Whitehead’s cosmologies in “The Problem of Motion” (Reference Hoskyn1929).

15 Northrop’s position here is similar to Einstein’s response to Bridgman. See Einstein (1949, 679): “In order to be able to consider a logical system as physical theory it is not necessary to demand that all of its assertions can be … ‘tested’ ‘operationally’; de facto this has never yet been achieved … In order to be able to consider a theory as a physical theory it is only necessary that it implies empirically testable assertions.”

16 Naturally, this development did not start in the 1920s. American philosophers had also responded to scientific advances before the rise of relativity. Still, the Royal Society announcement appears to have given new impetus to American philosophy of science. Moreover, it changed the nature of the debate about science because philosophical discussions about Einstein’s theory were often focused on questions about meaning and verification.

17 Both labels have their origin in the 19th century. The Monist had used the subtitle “Devoted to the Philosophy of Science” since 1898; the Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods promoted itself as a periodical “in the field of scientific philosophy” in the 1900s. Labels such as “philosophy of science,” “scientific philosophy,” “analysis of science,” “mathematical philosophy,” and “logic of science” were often used alongside each other, and different philosophers seem to have used these terms in slightly different ways.

18 October 2, 1928, Wiener Kreis Archiv (hereafter, WKA), 118/Stua-1, Haarlem.

19 Robert A. Millikan to Edgar J. Fisher, December 7, 1938, cited in Reisch and Tuboly (Reference Reisch and Tamas Tuboly2023).

20 Carnap to Reichenbach, May 7, 1923, Hans Reichenbach Papers (hereafter, HRP), 016-28-12, Archives of Scientific Philosophy, University of Pittsburgh.

21 Interestingly, the philosophy of relativity played a far less important role in bridging the gap between European and British philosophy. British discussions about the philosophical implications of relativity had emerged a bit earlier and had already lost momentum in the late 1920s. Sanchez-Ron (2012, 78) speculates that the “momentum was not sustained” because British philosophy was more “academic” and because there were fewer “scientists with deeply rooted philosophical interests.” One could add that philosophical publications by British physicists (e.g., Jeans and Eddington) were often criticized by philosophers in the United Kingdom (e.g., Stebbing Reference Stebbing1937). I thank an anonymous reviewer for this suggestion.

22 Northrop to Reichenbach, Jan. 5, 1932, HRP, 014-57-12.

23 See Verhaegh (2020, 2023). Lewis is an interesting figure because he proposed a relativized (or pragmatic) conception of the a priori that was quite similar to the perspective Carnap and Reichenbach had been developing in Europe. In a letter to Schlick, Feigl even called Lewis’s position “barely distinguishable from our positivism” (Dec. 6, 1930, Moritz Schlick Papers, Noord-Hollands Archief, 99/Fei-17). Interestingly, Lewis had used Einstein’s definition of simultaneity as an illustration for his claim that “the fundamental laws of any science … are a priori because they formulate just such definitive concepts … by which alone investigation becomes possible” (Reference Lewis1923, 173). See Lewis (1923) and Franco (Reference Franco2020) for a discussion.

References

Bergson, Henri. 1922. Durée et simultanéité. Paris: Alcan.Google Scholar
Biezunski, Michel. 1987. “Einstein’s Reception in Paris in 1922.” In The Comparative Reception of Relativity, edited by Thomas, F. Glick, 169–88. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Birkhoff, George David. 1925. The Origin, Nature, and Influence of Relativity. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Bixler, Julius Seelye. 1930. “Professor Dewey Discusses Religion.” Harvard Theological Review 23 (3):213–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bridgman, Percy Williams. 1927. The Logic of Modern Physics. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Bridgman, Percy Williams. 1960. “Introduction.” In Stallo, Johann Bernhard, The Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics, edited by Bridgman, Percy Williams, viixxix. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Campbell, James. 2006. A Thoughtful Profession: The Early Years of the American Philosophical Association. Peru, IL: Open Court Google Scholar
Carmichael, Robert. 1912. The Theory of Relativity. New York: Wiley. Google Scholar
Carmichael, Robert. 1927. “Philosophical Implications of the Theory.” In A Debate on the Theory of Relativity, edited by Bryan, William Lowe, 128–50. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Carmichael, Robert. 1930. The Logic of Discovery. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Carr, Herbert Wildon. 1920. The General Principle of Relativity in Its Philosophical and Historical Aspect. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Carr, Herbert Wildon, Percy Nunn, T., Whitehead, Alfred N., and Wrinch, Dorothy. 1922. “Discussion: The Idealistic Interpretation of Einstein’s Theory.” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 22 (1):123–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Carus, Paul. 1913. The Principle of Relativity in the Light of the Philosophy of Science. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
Cohen, Morris Raphael. 1913. “The New Realism.” Journal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific Methods 10 (8):197214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Costello, Harry T. 1931. “Review of Contemporary American Philosophy: Personal Statements by G. P. Adams and W. P. Montague.Journal of Philosophy 28:244–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Creighton, James Edwin. 1902. “The Purposes of a Philosophical Association.” Philosophical Review 11 (3):219–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crelinsten, Jeffrey. 2006. Einstein’s Jury: The Race to Test Relativity. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Laguna, Theodore. 1922a. “The Nature of Space—I.” Journal of Philosophy 19 (15):393407 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Laguna, Theodore. 1922b. “The Nature of Space—II.” Journal of Philosophy 19 (16):421–40.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
De Laguna, Theodore. 1922c. “Point, Line, and Surface as Sets of Solids.” Journal of Philosophy 19 (17):449–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Demoures, François-Xavier. 2007. “Relativité et relativisme: La réception de la théorie d’Einstein.” Tracés, 12:153–65.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Desmet, Ronald. 2007. “Whitehead and the British Reception of Einstein’s Relativity.” Process Studies Supplement Issue, 11:144.Google Scholar
Einstein, Albert. 1917. On the Special and General Theory of Relativity. London: Methuen and Co.Google Scholar
Einstein, Albert. 1918. “Dialog über Einwände gegen die Relativitätstheorie.” Naturwissenschaften 6:697702.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Einstein, Albert. 1949. “Remarks to the Essays Appearing in this Collective Volume.” In Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist: The Library of Living Philosophers, vol. VII, edited by Schilpp, Paul Arthur, 663–88. New York: Harper and Row.Google Scholar
Feigl, Herbert. 1969. “The Wiener Kreis in America.” In The Intellectual Migration: Europe and America 1930–1960, edited by Fleming, Donald and Bailyn, Bernard, 630–73. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
Franco, Paul. 2020. “Hans Reichenbach’s and C. I. Lewis’s Kantian Philosophies of Science.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 80:6271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Friedman, Michael. 1999. Reconsidering Logical Positivism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Glick, Thomas F., ed. 1987. The Comparative Reception of Relativity. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Stanley J. 1984. Understanding Relativity: Origin and Impact of a Scientific Revolution. Boston: Birkhäuser.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Goldberg, Stanley J. 1988. “What Instruments Measure and What People Believe: Reflections on Interpretations of the Michelson-Morley Experiment.” AIP Conference Proceedings 179 (1):7895.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gordin, Wolf. 1926. “The Philosophy of Relativity.” Journal of Philosophy 23 (19):517–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Haldane, Viscount. 1921. The Reign of Relativity. London: John Murray.Google Scholar
Henderson, Harold. 1993. Catalyst for Controversy: Paul Carus of Open Court. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.Google Scholar
Herbert, Christopher. 2001. Victorian Relativity: Radical Thought and Scientific Discovery. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Holt, Edwin B., Marvin, Walter T., William Pepperell Montague, Ralph Barton Perry, Pitkin, Walter B., and Gleason Spaulding, Edward, eds. 1912. The New Realism. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Hook, Sidney. 1930. “A Personal Impression of Contemporary German Philosophy.” Journal of Philosophy 27 (6):141–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hoskyn, Fred. 1929. “The Problem of Motion.” Journal of Philosophy 26 (13):337–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howard, Don. 1984. “Realism and Conventionalism in Einstein’s Philosophy of Science: The Einstein-Schlick Correspondence.” Philosophia Naturalis 21 (2–4):616–29.Google Scholar
Hu, Danian. 2007. “The Reception of Relativity in China.” Isis 98 (3):539–57.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Katzav, Joel, and Vaesen, Krist. 2022. “The Rise of Logical Empiricist Philosophy of Science and the Fate of Speculative Philosophy of Science.” HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 12 (2):327–58.Google Scholar
Kevles, Daniel J. 1979. The Physicists: The History of a Scientific Community in Modern America. New York: Vintage Books.Google Scholar
Keyser, Cassius Jackson. 1922. Mathematical Philosophy. New York: E. P. Dutton & Company.Google Scholar
Kuklick, Bruce. 2001. A History of Philosophy in America, 1720–2000. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
Kurz, Paul. 1966. American Philosophy in the 20th Century. New York: MacMillan.Google Scholar
Langer, Susanne K. 1930. “Review of Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre by Hans Reichenbach.” Journal of Philosophy 27 (22):609–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Clarence Irving. 1923. “A Pragmatic Conception of the A Priori.” Journal of Philosophy 20 (7):169–77.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Clarence Irving. 1925. “Review of Scientific Thought by C. D. Broad.” Philosophical Review 34 (4):406–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, Gilbert N., and Tolman, Richard C.. 1909. “The Principle of Relativity, and Non-Newtonian Mechanics.” Proceedings of the AAAS 44 (25):711–24.Google Scholar
Lovejoy, Arthur Oncken. 1930. “The Dialectical Argument against Absolute Simultaneity (I).” Journal of Philosophy 27 (33):617–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lovejoy, Arthur Oncken. 1931. “The Paradox of the Time-Retarding Journey (I).” Philosophical Review 40 (1):4868.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Magie, William Francis. 1912. “The Primary Concepts of Physics.” Science 35 (895):281–93.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Margenau, Henry. 1931. “Causality and Modern Physics.” The Monist 41 (1):136.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
McGilvary, Evander Bradley. 1931. “Dialectical Arguments against Relative Simultaneity.” Journal of Philosophy 28 (16):421–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Meyerson, Emile. 1925. La deduction relativiste. Paris: Payot.Google Scholar
Missner, Marshall. 1985. “Why Einstein Became Famous in America.” Social Studies of Science 15 (2):267–91.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montague, William Pepperell. 1902. “Professor Royce’s Refutation of Realism.” Philosophical Review 11 (1):4355.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Montague, William Pepperell. 1912. “A Realistic Theory of Truth and Error.” In The New Realism, edited by Edwin, B. Holt, Marvin, Walter T., Montague, William Pepperell, Perry, Ralph Barton, Pitkin, Walter B., and Spaulding, Edward Gleason, 252302. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Montague, William Pepperell. 1924. “The Einstein Theory and a Possible Alternative.” Philosophical Review 33 (2):143–70.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
More, Louis T. 1909. “Atomic Theories and Modern Physics.” Hibbert Journal 7 (4):864–81.Google Scholar
More, Louis T. 1910. “The Metaphysical Tendencies of Modern Physics.” Hibbert Journal 8 (4):800–17.Google Scholar
More, Louis T. 1911. “On the Recent Theories of Electricity.” London, Edinburgh, and Dublin Philosophical Magazine and Journal of Science 21 (122):196218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Morris, Charles W. 1935. “Some Aspects of Recent American Scientific Philosophy.” Erkenntnis 5 (1):142–51.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Ernest. 1929. “Nature and Convention.” Journal of Philosophy 26 (7):169–82.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northrop, Filmer Stuart Cuckow. 1925. “Relativity and the Relation of Science to Philosophy.” The Monist 35 (1):126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northrop, Filmer Stuart Cuckow. 1928. “The Theory of Relativity and the First Principles of Science.” Journal of Philosophy 25 (16):421–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northrop, Filmer Stuart Cuckow. 1931. “Review of Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre by Hans Reichenbach.Philosophical Review 40:281285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Northrop, Filmer Stuart Cuckow. 1939. “The Significance of Epistemic Correlations in Scientific Method.” Journal of Unified Science 8:434–37.Google Scholar
Ormond, Alexander Thomas. 1906. Concepts of Philosophy. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Perry, Ralph Barton. 1902. “Prof. Royce’s Refutation of Realism and Pluralism.” The Monist 12 (3):446–58.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Perry, Ralph Barton. 1928. “Peace Without Victory in Philosophy.Philosophy 3:300–12.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pratt-Hartman, Ian. 2007. “First-Order Mereotopology.” In Handbook of Spatial Logics, edited by Aiello, Marco, Pratt-Hartmann, Ian, and van Benthem, Johan, 1398. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reeves, Barbara. 1987. “Einstein Politicized: The Early Reception of Relativity in Italy.” In The Comparative Reception of Relativity, edited by Thomas, F. Glick, 189229. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reichenbach, Hans. 1920. Relativitätstheorie und Erkenntnis Apriori. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Reisch, George A., and Tamas Tuboly, Adam. 2023. “Reviving the Unity of Science Movement: Philipp Frank’s Journey to Harvard.” Unpublished manuscript.Google Scholar
Russell, Bertrand. 1926. “Relativity: Philosophical Consequences.” In Encyclopedia Britannica, 13th ed., 331–32. London: Encyclopaedia Britannica.Google Scholar
Ryckman, Thomas. 2005. The Reign of Relativity: Philosophy in Physics 1915–1925. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ryckman, Thomas. 2017. Einstein. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Sanchez-Ron, José M. 2012. “The Early Reception of Einstein’s Relativity among British Philosophers.” In Einstein and the Changing Worldviews of Physics, edited by Lehner, Christoph Renn, Jürgen and Schemmel, Matthias 73–116. New York: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schilpp, Paul Arthur. 1930. “Survey of American Philosophy.” Journal of Philosophical Studies 5 (18):270–78.Google Scholar
Schlick, Moritz. 1922. “Die Relativitätstheorie in der Philosophie.” Verhandlungen der Gesellschaft Deutscher Naturforscher under Ärzte 87:5869.Google Scholar
Smart, Harold R. 1925. “Review of La Déduction Relativiste by E. Myerson.” Philosophical Review 34 (5):511–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Smith, William Benjamin. 1921. “Relativity and Its Philosophic Interpretations.” The Monist 31 (4):481511.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Stallo, Johann Bernhard. 1882. The Concepts and Theories of Modern Physics. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, and Co. Google Scholar
Stebbing, Susan. 1937. Philosophy and the Physicists. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
ten Hagen, Sjang L. 2020. “The Local versus the Global in the History of Relativity: The Case of Belgium.” Science in Context 33 (3):227–50.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Thilly, Frank. 1926. “Contemporary American Philosophy.” Philosophical Review 35 (6):522–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Van de Walle, W. Edwin. 1928. “Review: The Logic of Modern Physics by P. W. Bridgman.” The Philosophical Review 37 (3):285–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Varzi, Achille. 2007. “Spatial Reasoning and Ontology: Parts, Wholes, and Locations.” In Handbook of Spatial Logics, edited by Aiello, Marco, Pratt-Hartmann, Ian, and van Benthem, Johan, 9451038. Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Verhaegh, Sander. Forthcoming. “Logical Positivism: The History of a ‘Caricature’.” Isis: A Journal of the History of Science Society.Google Scholar
Verhaegh, Sander. 2020. “The American Reception of Logical Positivism: First Encounters, 1929–1932.” HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 10 (1):106–42.Google Scholar
Verhaegh, Sander. 2023. “Carnap and Quine: First Encounters (1932–36).” In The Philosophical Project of Carnap and Quine, edited by Morris, Sean, 1131. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Whitehead, Alfred North. 1929. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
Wilson, Daniel J. 1990. Science, Community, and the Transformation of American Philosophy. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Figure 0

Table 1. Selection of Papers on Relativity Theory Published in Three Prominent American Philosophy Journals between 1921 and 1930

Figure 1

Table 2. Selection of Reviews of Books on Relativity Theory in the Journal of Philosophy and Philosophical Review between 1921 and 1930