Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-q99xh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-25T06:48:04.511Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Push the Button

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

The article discusses a well-known type of counterexample to Causal Decision Theory (CDT), in which CDT recommends an option that probably causes the best outcome while itself being evidence that it causes the worst. Intuition disagrees. Many philosophers accept that this justifies either modifying CDT or dropping it altogether. I argue to the contrary that (a) if intuition is right about this case, then transitivity of preference must be violated in another, but (b) this violation is untenable. I conclude that CDT stands.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

The author wishes to thank Rachel Briggs and Huw Price for helpful discussion and two Philosophy of Science referees for helpful comments. The author began this article while on a Leverhulme Trust Research Fellowship, and he gratefully acknowledges the trust's support.

References

Anand, Paul. 1993. Foundations of Rational Choice under Risk. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
Arntzenius, Frank. 2008. “No Regrets; or, Edith Piaf Revamps Decision Theory.” Erkenntnis 68 (2): 277–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Binmore, Kenneth. 2009. Rational Decisions. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Edgington, Dorothy. 2011. “Conditionals, Causation and Decision.” Analytic Philosophy 52 (2): 7587.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Egan, Andrew. 2007. “Some Counterexamples to Causal Decision Theory.” Philosophical Review 116 (1): 93114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Alan. 1992. “Weakly Self-Ratifying Strategies: Comments on McClennen.” Philosophical Studies 65 (1–2): 217–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gibbard, Alan, and Harper, William. 1978/1988. “Counterfactuals and Two Kinds of Expected Utility.” In Foundations and Applications of Decision Theory, ed. Hooker, Clifford A., Leach, James J., and McClennen, Edward F., 125–62. Dordrecht: Reidel. Repr. in Peter Gärdenfors and Nils-Eric Sahlin, eds. Decision, Probability and Utility (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).Google Scholar
Gustafsson, Johan. 2011. “A Note in Defence of Ratificationism.” Erkenntnis 75 (1): 147–50.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nagel, Thomas. 1970. The Possibility of Altruism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Nozick, Robert. 1970. “Newcomb's Problem and Two Principles of Choice.” In Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel, ed. Rescher, Nicholas, 114–46. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
Wedgwood, Ralph. 2011. “Gandalf's Solution to the Newcomb Problem.” Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-011-9900-1.CrossRefGoogle Scholar