Hostname: page-component-78c5997874-8bhkd Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-03T05:31:32.375Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Philosophical Scrutiny of Evidence of Risks: From Bioethics to Bioevidence

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

We argue that a responsible analysis of today's evidence-based risk assessments and risk debates in biology demands a critical or metascientific scrutiny of the uncertainties, assumptions, and threats of error along the manifold steps in risk analysis. Without an accompanying methodological critique, neither sensitivity to social and ethical values, nor conceptual clarification alone, suffices. In this view, restricting the invitation for philosophical involvement to those wearing a “bioethicist” label precludes the vitally important role philosophers of science may be able to play as bioevidentialists. The goal of this paper is to give a brief and partial sketch of how a metascientific scrutiny of risk evidence might work.

Type
Can Philosophy Offer Help in Resolving Contemporary Biological Controversies?
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

References

Burgman, M. (2005), Risks and Decisions for Conservation and Environmental Management. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calabrese, E. J. (2005), “Hormetic Dose-Response Relationships in Immunology: Occurrence, Qualitative Features of the Dose-Response, Mechanistic Foundations, and Clinical Implications,” Critical Reviews in Toxicology 35:89295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calabrese, E. J., and Baldwin, L. A. (2003), “The Hormetic Dose-Response Model Is More Common than the Threshold Model in Toxicology,” Toxicological Sciences 71:246250.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Calabrese, E. J., Baldwin, L. A., and Holland, C. D. (1999), “Hormesis: A Highly Generalizable and Reproducible Phenomenon with Important Implications for Risk Assessment,” Risk Analysis 19:261281.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Cranor, C. F. (1993), Regulating Toxic Substances: A Philosophy of Science and the Law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Crump, K. (2001), “Evaluating the Evidence for Hormesis: A Statistical Perspective,” Critical Reviews in Toxicology 31:669679.CrossRefGoogle ScholarPubMed
Elliott, K. C. (2006), “A Novel Account of Scientific Anomaly: Help for the Dispute Over Low-Dose Biochemical,” Philosophy of Science 73 (5), in this issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Marvier, M. (2002), “Improving Risk Assessment for Nontarget Safety of Transgenic Crops,” Ecological Applications 12:11191124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (1985), “Increasing Public Participation in Controversies Involving Hazards: The Values of Metastatistical Rules,” Science, Technology, and Human Values 10:5568.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (1988), “Toward a More Objective Understanding of the Evidence of Carcinogenic Risk,” in Fine, Arthur and Leplin, Jarrett (eds.), PSA 1988: Proceedings of the 1988 Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association, Vol. 2. East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association, 489503.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (1991), “Sociological vs. Metascientific Views of Risk Assessment,” in Mayo and Hollander 1991, 249279.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (1996), Error and the Growth of Experimental Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (2004), “An Error-Statistical Philosophy of Evidence,” in Taper, M. and Lele, S. (eds.), The Nature of Scientific Evidence: Statistical, Philosophical, and Empirical Consideration. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. G. (2005), “Evidence as Passing Severe Tests: Highly Probed vs. Highly Proved,” in Achinstein, P. (ed.), Scientific Evidence. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. G., and Cox, D. R. (2006), “Frequentist Statistics as a Theory of Inductive Inference,” in Optimality: The Second Erich L. Lehmann Symposium, Vol. 49, Lecture Notes-Monograph Series. Beachwood, OH: Institute of Mathematical Statistics.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G., and Hollander, R. D., eds. (1991), Acceptable Evidence: Science and Values in Risk Management. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. G., and Kruse, M. (2001), “Principles of Inference and Their Consequences,” in Cornfield, D. and Williamson, J. (eds.), Foundations of Bayesianism. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 381403.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G., and Spanos, A. (2004), “Methodology in Practice: Statistical Misspecification Testing,” Philosophy of Science 71:10071025.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G., and Spanos, A. (2006), “Severe Testing as a Basic Concept in a Neyman-Pearson Philosophy of Induction,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 57:323357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. G., and Spanos, A. (2007), “Risks to Health and Risks to Science: The Need for a Responsible ‘Bioevidential' Scrutiny,” Human and Experimental Toxicology, forthcoming.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
NRC (National Research Council) (1983), Risk Assessment in the Federal Government. Washington, DC: National Academy Press.Google Scholar
Shrader-Frechette, K. (1991), Risk and Rationality. Berkeley: University of California Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shrader-Frechette, K. (2006), “Comparativist Philosophy of Science and Population Viability Assessment in Biology: Helping Resolve Scientific Controversy,” Philosophy of Science 73 (5), in this issue.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Thompson, P. B. (2006), “How Risky Are Genetically Engineered Crops? How Philosophers Can Help Answer the Question,” Philosophy of Science 73 (5), in this issue.Google Scholar