Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-t8hqh Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-27T22:43:13.709Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Phenomena and Objects of Research in the Cognitive and Behavioral Sciences

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 January 2022

Abstract

It is commonly held that research efforts in the cognitive and behavioral sciences are mainly directed toward providing explanations and that phenomena figure into scientific practice qua explananda. I contend that these assumptions convey a skewed picture of the research practices in question and of the role played by phenomena. I argue that experimental research often aims at exploring and describing “objects of research” and that phenomena can figure as components of, and as evidence for, such objects. I situate my analysis within the existing literature and illustrate it with examples from memory research.

Type
Cognitive Sciences
Copyright
Copyright © The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Previous versions of this article were presented at the Universities of Hannover, Bielefeld, Wuppertal, and Graz, as well as the 2015 meeting of the European Philosophy of Science Association in Düsseldorf (Germany). A more recent version was presented at the Technische Universität Berlin in July 2016. The author would like to thank the members of these audiences, as well as colleagues who attended my talk at the 2016 meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association in Atlanta, for their very helpful questions and comments.

References

Baddeley, Alan, and Hitch, D. J. 1974. “Working Memory.” In The Psychology of Learning and Motivation: Advances in Research and Theory, ed. Bower, Gordon, 8:4778. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Beaman, C. P. 2000. “The Size and Nature of a Chunk.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24:118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Bechtel, William. 2008. Mental Mechanisms: Philosophical Perspectives on Cognitive Neuroscience. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
Bechtel, William, and Richardson, Robert. 1993. Discovering Complexity: Decomposition and Localization as Strategies in Scientific Research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Bogen, James, and Woodward, James. 1988. “Saving the Phenomena.” Philosophical Review 97 (3): 303–52.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chow, Sheldon. 2015. “The Gap between Psychological Explanation and Mechanistic Explanation.” Paper presented at the 2015 meeting of the European Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
Cowan, Nelson. 2000. “The Magical Number 4 in Short-Term Memory: A Reconsideration of Mental Storage Capacity.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24:87115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl. 2007. Explaining the Brain: The Mosaic Unity of the Cognitive Neurosciences. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Craver, Carl, and Darden, Lindley. 2001. “Discovering Mechanisms in Neurobiology: The Case of Spatial Memory.” In Theory and Method in the Neurosciences, ed. Machamer, Peter, Grush, Rick, and McLaughlin, Peter, 112–37. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.Google Scholar
Machamer, Peter, Grush, Rick, and McLaughlin, Peter 2013. In Search of Mechanisms: Discovery across the Life Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
Cummins, Robert. 2000. “‘How Does It Work?’ versus ‘What Are the Laws?’: Two Conceptions of Psychological Explanation.” In Explanation and Cognition, ed. Keil, Frank and Wilson, Robert, 117–44. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
Darden, Lindley. 2006. Reasoning in Biological Discoveries. New York: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feest, Uljana. 2011a. “Remembering (Short-Term) Memory: Oscillations of an Epistemic Thing.” Erkenntnis 75:391411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Feest, Uljana 2011b. “What Exactly Is Stabilized When Phenomena Are Stabilized?Synthese 182:5771.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Hacking, Ian. 1983. Representing and Intervening. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Halford, Graeme, Phillips, Steven, and Wilson, William. 2000. “Processing Capacity Limits Are Not Explained by Storage Limits.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24:123–25.Google Scholar
Miller, George. 1956. “The Magical Number Seven, Plus or Minus Two: Some Limits on Our Capacity for Processing Information.” Psychological Review 101 (2): 343–52.Google Scholar
Milner, P. 2000. “Magical Attention.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24:131.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Pascual-Leone, Juan. 2000. “If the Magical Number Is 4, How Does One Account for Operations within Working Memory?Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24:136–38.Google Scholar
Schubert, Torsten, and Frensch, Peter A. 2000. “How Unitary Is the Capacity-Limited Attentional Focus?Behavioral and Brain Sciences 24:146–47.Google Scholar
Tversky, Barbara. 1993. “Cognitive Maps, Cognitive Collages, and Spatial Mental Models.” In Spatial Information Theory: A Theoretical Basis for GIS, ed. Frank, Andrew U. and Campari, Irene, 1424. Berlin: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wilson, Mark. 2006. Wandering Significance: An Essay on Conceptual Behavior. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Woodward, Jim. 1989. “Data and Phenomena.” Synthese 79:393472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar