Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-dlnhk Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-04T10:11:39.391Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

On the Metatheoretical Nature of Carnap's Philosophy

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Bryan G. Norton*
Affiliation:
New College of the University of South Florida

Abstract

Rudolf Carnap defended two quite different critiques of traditional philosophy: in addition to the much discussed verifiability criterion, he also proposed a critique based upon “formalizability.” Formalizability rests upon the principle of tolerance plus an acceptance of a linguistic methodology. Standard interpreters of Carnap (e.g., [7] and [8]) assume that the principle of tolerance (and, hence, formalizability) gains its argumentative support from verificationism. Carnap, in fact, kept the two critiques separate and independent. Indeed, verificationism is even, in spirit, inconsistent with tolerance. If the formalizability approach is emphasized, traditional metaphysics is reconstructed, not banished. Philosophical disputes remain rationally decidable, but metatheoretical in nature. Two results follow: Carnap's metaphilosophy cannot be rejected merely on the basis of rejections of verifiability. Second, Carnap's conclusion that all philosophy concerns language provides no reason for despair.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1977 by the Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

I have benefited from the suggestions of Peter McCormick, Gresham Riley, Charles Morris, and Spencer Carr, all of whom have read previous drafts of this paper.

References

REFERENCES

Carnap, R.Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology.” In Meaning and Necessity. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1956. Pages 205221.Google Scholar
Carnap, R.Intellectual Autobiography,” in The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap. Edited by Schilpp, P. A. LaSalle: Open Court, 1963.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. Introduction to Semantics. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1943.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. The Logical Syntax of Language. Translated by Smeaton, . New York: Humanities Press, 1937.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. Philosophy and Logical Syntax. In Readings in Twentieth Century Philosophy. Edited by Alston, W. P. and Nakhnikian, G. New York: Macmillan, The Free Press of Glencoe, 1964. Pages 424460.Google Scholar
Carnap, R. Testability and Meaning. New Haven: Whitlock's, Inc., 1954.Google Scholar
Cornman, J. Metaphysics, Reference, and Language. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1966.Google Scholar
Goldstick, D.The Tolerance of Rudolf Carnap.” Australasian Journal of Philosophy 49 (1971): 250261.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Quine, W. V. O. The Ways of Paradox and Other Essays. New York: Random House, 1966.Google Scholar
Rorty, R. The Linguistic Turn. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1970.Google Scholar
Wisdom, J.Logical Constructions (V)”. Mind 42 (1933): 186202.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Wittgenstein, L. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. Translated by Pears, D. F. and McGuinness, B. F. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961.Google Scholar