Hostname: page-component-586b7cd67f-2plfb Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-11-23T23:31:31.988Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

Novel Evidence and Severe Tests

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

Deborah G. Mayo*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University
*
Send reprint requests to the author, Department of Philosophy, Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University, Blacksburg, VA 24061.

Abstract

While many philosophers of science have accorded special evidential significance to tests whose results are “novel facts”, there continues to be disagreement over both the definition of novelty and why it should matter. The view of novelty favored by Giere, Lakatos, Worrall and many others is that of use-novelty: An accordance between evidence e and hypothesis h provides a genuine test of h only if e is not used in h's construction. I argue that what lies behind the intuition that novelty matters is the deeper intuition that severe tests matter. I set out a criterion of severity akin to the notion of a test's power in Neyman-Pearson statistics. I argue that tests which are use-novel may fail to be severe, and tests that are severe may fail to be use-novel. I discuss the 1919 eclipse data as a severe test of Einstein's law of gravity.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © 1991 The Philosophy of Science Association

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

The research for this paper took place during tenure of a National Endowment for the Humanities Summer Stipend Fellowship and a National Endowment for the Humanities Fellowship for College Teachers. I gratefully acknowledge that support. Numerous stimulating discussions with Alan Musgrave were integral to formulating the ideas in this paper. I owe special thanks to George Barnard for insights into the statistical analysis of the 1919 eclipse data. For their valuable comments and criticism, I thank Dick Burian, Stephen Brush, Ronald Giere, Marjorie Grene, Larry Laudan, Ronald Laymon, Isaac Levi, Harlan Miller, Karl Popper, J. D. Trout, and John Worrall. Revisions were carried out while visiting the Center for Philosophy of Science at the University of Pittsburgh. I am grateful for the Center's stimulating environment, and for immensely helpful discussions on this paper with John Earman, Clark Glymour, Adolf Grünbaum, and Wesley Salmon. Versions of this paper have been given at the University of Hawaii, University of Maryland, and University of Pittsburgh.

References

Anderson, A. (1919), “The Displacement of Light Rays Passing Near the Sun”, Nature 104: 354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Anderson, A. (1920), “Deflection of Light During a Solar Eclipse”, Nature 104: 436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Campbell, R. and Vinci, T. (1983), “Novel Confirmation”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 34: 315341.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Dyson, E. W.; Eddington, A. S.; and Davidson, C. (1923), “A Determination of the Deflection of Light by the Sun's Gravitational Field, from Observations made at the Total Eclipse of May 29, 1919”, Memoirs of the Royal Astronomical Society 62: 291333.Google Scholar
Earman, J. and Glymour, C. (1980), “Relativity and Eclipses: The British Eclipse Expeditions of 1919 and Their Predecessors”, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 11: 4985.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eddington, A. (1918), “Gravitation and the Principle of Relativity”, Nature 101: 3436.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Eddington, A. (1919), “Joint Eclipse Meeting of the Royal Astronomical Society”, Observatory 42: 389398.Google Scholar
Eddington, A. (1935), Space, Time and Gravitation, An Outline of the General Relativity Theory. Reprint. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
Gardner, M. (1982), “Predicting Novel Facts”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 33: 115.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1969), “Bayesian Statistics and Biased Procedures”, Synthese 20: 371387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Giere, R. (1983), “Testing Theoretical Hypotheses”, in J. Earman (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 10, Testing Scientific Theories. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, pp. 269298.Google Scholar
Giere, R. (1984), Understanding Scientific Reasoning. 2d ed. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.Google Scholar
Glymour, C. (1980), Theory and Evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
Glymour, C.; Scheines, R.; Spirtes, P. and Kelly, K. (1987), Discovering Causal Structure: Artificial Intelligence, Philosophy of Science, and Statistical Modeling. Orlando: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1979), “Is Freudian Psychoanalytic Theory Pseudo-Scientific by Karl Popper's Criterion of Demarcation?”, American Philosophical Quarterly 16: 131141.Google Scholar
Grünbaum, A. (1989), “The Degeneration of Popper's Theory of Demarcation”, in F. D'Agostino and I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Freedom and Rationality: Essays in Honor of John Watkins. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, pp. 141161.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. (1984), “Bayesianism and Support by Novel Facts”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35: 245251.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Howson, C. and Urbach, P. (1989), Scientific Reasoning: The Bayesian Approach. Lasalle, IL: Open Court.Google Scholar
Jeffreys, H. (1919a), Contribution to “Discussion on the Theory of Relativity”, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 80: 116.Google Scholar
Jeffreys, H. (1919b), “On the Crucial Test of Einstein's Theory of Gravitation”, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 80: 138154.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lindemann, F. A. (1919), Contribution to “Discussion on the Theory of Relativity”, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 80: 114.Google Scholar
Lindley, D. V. (1971), “The Estimation of Many Parameters”, in V. P. Godambe and S. A. Sprott (eds.), Foundations of Statistical Inference. Toronto: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, pp. 435447.Google Scholar
Lodge, O. (1919), Contribution to “Discussion on the Theory of Relativity”, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society, 80: 106109.Google Scholar
Maher, P. (1988), “Prediction, Accommodation, and the Logic of Discovery”, in A. Fine and J. Leplin (eds.), PSA 1988, vol. 1. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 273285.Google Scholar
Mayo, D. (1981), “Testing Statistical Testing”, in J. C. Pitt (ed.), Philosophy in Economics: Papers Deriving from and Related to a Workshop on Testability and Explanation in Economics held at Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University, 1979. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 175203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. (1985), “Behavioristic, Evidentialist, and Learning Models of Statistical Testing”, Philosophy of Science 52: 493516.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Mayo, D. (1988), “Toward a More Objective Understanding of the Evidence of Carcinogenic Risk”, in A. Fine and J. Leplin (eds.), PSA 1988, vol. 2. East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 489503.Google Scholar
Moyer, D. (1979), “Revolution in Science: The 1919 Eclipse Test of General Relativity”, in A. Perlmutter and L. Scott, (eds.), On the Path of Albert Einstein. New York: Plenum Press, pp. 55102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1974), “Logical versus Historical Theories of Confirmation”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 25: 123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1978), “Evidential Support, Falsification, Heuristics, and Anarchism”, in G. Radnitzky and G. Andersson (eds.), Progress and Rationality in Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 181201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Musgrave, A. (1989), “Deductive Heuristics”, in K. Gavroglu, Y. Goudaroulis, and P. Nicolacopoulos (eds.), Imre Lakatos and Theories of Scientific Change. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, pp. 1532.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nature. (1920–1921). Volume 106.Google Scholar
Newall, H. F. (1919), Contribution to “Joint Eclipse Meeting of the Royal Society and the Royal Astronomical Society”, The Observatory 42: 395396.Google Scholar
Newall, H. F. (1920), “Note on the Physical Aspect of the Einstein Prediction”, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 80: 2225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Nickles, T. (1987), “Lakatosian Heuristics and Epistemic Support”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38: 181205.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Popper, K. (1962), Conjectures and Refutations. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1974), “Replies to My Critics”, in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), The Philosophy of Karl Popper. Book 2. Lasalle, IL: Open Court, pp. 9611197.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1979), Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
Popper, K. (1983), Realism and the Aim of Science. Totowa, NJ: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
Redhead, M. (1986), “Novelty and Confirmation”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37: 115118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Rosenkrantz, R. (1977), Inference, Method and Decision: Towards a Bayesian Philosophy of Science. Boston: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Schuster, A. (1920), “The Influence of Small Changes of Temperature on Atmospheric Refraction”, Proceedings, Physical Society of London 32: 135140.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
von Klüber, H. (1960), “The Determination of Einstein's Light-Deflection in the Gravitational Field of the Sun”, in A. Beer (ed.), Vistas on Astronomy 3, pp. 4777.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1978a), “Research Programmes, Empirical Support, and the Duhem Problem: Replies to Criticism”, in G. Radnitzky and G. Andersson (eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 58, Progress and Rationality in Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 321338.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. (1978b), “The Ways in Which the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes Improves on Popper's Methodology”, in G. Radnitzky and G. Andersson (eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Vol. 58, Progress and Rationality in Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 4570.Google Scholar
Worrall, J. (1985), “Scientific Discovery and Theory-Confirmation”, in J. C. Pitt (ed.), Change and Progress in Modern Science: Papers Related to and Arising from the Fourth International Conference on History and Philosophy of Science. Dordrecht: Reidel, pp. 301331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Worrall, J. (1989), “Fresnel, Poisson and the White Spot: The Role of Successful Predictions in the Acceptance of Scientific Theories”, in D. Gooding, T. Pinch and S. Schaffer (eds.), The Uses of Experiment: Studies in the Natural Sciences. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press, pp. 135157.Google Scholar
Zahar, E. (1973), “Why Did Einstein's Programme Supersede Lorentz's? (I) and (II)The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 24: 95125, 223–262.CrossRefGoogle Scholar