Hostname: page-component-cd9895bd7-dzt6s Total loading time: 0 Render date: 2024-12-24T18:31:56.215Z Has data issue: false hasContentIssue false

A Nonpragmatic Vindication of Probabilism

Published online by Cambridge University Press:  01 April 2022

James M. Joyce*
Affiliation:
Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan

Abstract

The pragmatic character of the Dutch book argument makes it unsuitable as an “epistemic” justification for the fundamental probabilist dogma that rational partial beliefs must conform to the axioms of probability. To secure an appropriately epistemic justification for this conclusion, one must explain what it means for a system of partial beliefs to accurately represent the state of the world, and then show that partial beliefs that violate the laws of probability are invariably less accurate than they could be otherwise. The first task can be accomplished once we realize that the accuracy of systems of partial beliefs can be measured on a gradational scale that satisfies a small set of formal constraints, each of which has a sound epistemic motivation. When accuracy is measured in this way it can be shown that any system of degrees of belief that violates the axioms of probability can be replaced by an alternative system that obeys the axioms and yet is more accurate in every possible world. Since epistemically rational agents must strive to hold accurate beliefs, this establishes conformity with the axioms of probability as a norm of epistemic rationality whatever its prudential merits or defects might be.

Type
Research Article
Copyright
Copyright © Philosophy of Science Association 1998

Access options

Get access to the full version of this content by using one of the access options below. (Log in options will check for institutional or personal access. Content may require purchase if you do not have access.)

Footnotes

Send requests for reprints to the author, Department of Philosophy, University of Michigan, 435 South State Street, Ann Arbor, MI 48109–1003.

I have been helped and encouraged in the development of these ideas by Brad Armendt, Robert Batterman, Alan Code, David Christensen, Dan Farrell, Allan Gibbard, Alan Hajek, William Harper, Sally Haslanger, Mark Kaplan, Jeff Kasser, Louis Loeb, Gerhard Nuffer, Peter Railton, Gideon Rosen, Larry Sklar, Brian Skyrms, Bas van Fraassen, David Velleman, Peter Vranas, Nick White, Mark Wilson, Steve Yablo, and Lyle Zynda. Richard Jeffrey's influence on my thinking will be clear to anyone who knows his writings. Special thanks are also due to two anonymous referees from Philosophy of Science, whose splendidly detailed comments greatly improved the final version of this paper.

References

Anscombe, G. E. M. (1957), Intention. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
Brier, G. (1950) “Verification of Forecasts Expressed in Terms of Probability”, Monthly Weather Review 78: 13.2.0.CO;2>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Chisholm, R. (1977), Theory of Knowledge, 2nd ed. New York: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
de Finetti, B. (1974), Theory of Probability, vol. 1. New York: John Wiley and Sons.Google Scholar
Fine, T. (1973), Theories of Probability. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
Foley, R. (1987), The Theory of Epistemic Rationality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Forrest, P. (1989), “The Problem of Representing Incompletely Ordered Doxastic Systems”, Synthese 79: 1833.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Gardenfors, P. and Shalin, P. (1988), Decision, Probability, and Utility. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1986), “Probabilism and Induction”, Topoi 5: 5158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Jeffrey, R. (1992), “Probability and the Art of Judgment”, in Probability and the Art of Judgment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 4476.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kennedy, R. and Chihara, C. (1979) “The Dutch Book Argument: its Logical Flaws, its Subjective Sources”, Philosophical Studies 36: 1933.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Kraft, C., Pratt, J., and Seidenberg, A. (1959), “Intuitive Probability on Finite Sets”, Annals of Mathematical Statistics 30: 408419.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David (1988), “Desire as Belief”, Mind 97: 323332.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Lewis, David (1996), “Desire as Belief II”, Mind 105: 303313.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Maher, P. (1993), Betting on Theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Murphy, A. (1973), “A New Vector Partition of the Probability Score”, Journal of Applied Meteorology 12: 595600.2.0.CO;2>CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Ramsey, F. P. (1931), “Truth and Probability”, in Braithwaite, R. B. (ed.), The Foundations of Mathematics. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 156198.Google Scholar
Rosenkrantz, R. (1981), Foundations and Applications of Inductive Probability. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Press.Google Scholar
Salmon, W. (1988), “Dynamic Rationality: Propensity, Probability and Credence”, in Fetzer, J. H. (ed.), Probability and Causality. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 340.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Savage, L. (1971), “Elicitation of Personal Probabilities”, Journal of the American Statistical Association 66: 783801.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Scott, D. (1964), “Measurement Structures and Linear Inequalities”, Journal of Mathematical Psychology 1: 233247.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Seidenfeld, T. (1985), “Calibration, Coherence, and Scoring Rules”, Philosophy of Science 52: 274294.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Shimony, A. (1988), “An Adamite Derivation of the Calculus of Probability”, in Fetzer, J. H. (ed.), Probability and Causality. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 151161.Google Scholar
Skyrms, B. (1984), Pragmatics and Empiricism. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
Smith, M. (1987), “The Humean Theory of Motivation”, Mind 96: 3661.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
van Fraassen, B. (1983), “Calibration: A Frequency Justification for Personal Probability”, in Cohen, R. and Laudan, L. (eds.), Physics Philosophy and Psychoanalysis. Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 295319.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
Velleman, J. D. (1996), “The Possibility of Practical Reason,” Ethics 106: 694726.CrossRefGoogle Scholar